PREFACE
Ancient Greek philosophy was divided
into three sciences: physics, ethics, and logic. This division is perfectly
suitable to the nature of the thing; and the only improvement that can be made
in it is to add the principle on which it is based, so that we may both satisfy
ourselves of its completeness, and also be able to determine correctly the
necessary subdivisions.
All rational knowledge is either material or formal: the former
considers some object, the latter is concerned only with the form of the
understanding and of the reason itself, and with the universal laws of thought
in general without distinction of its objects. Formal philosophy is called
logic. Material philosophy, however, has to do with determinate objects and the
laws to which they are subject, is again twofold; for these laws are either laws
of nature or of freedom. The science of the former is physics, that of the
latter, ethics; they are also called natural philosophy and moral philosophy
respectively.
Logic cannot have any empirical part; that is, a part in which
the universal and necessary laws of thought should rest on grounds taken from
experience; otherwise it would not be logic, i.e., a canon for the understanding
or the reason, valid for all thought, and capable of demonstration. Natural and
moral philosophy, on the contrary, can each have their empirical part, since the
former has to determine the laws of nature as an object of experience; the
latter the laws of the human will, so far as it is affected by nature: the
former, however, being laws according to which everything does happen; the
latter, laws according to which everything ought to happen. Ethics, however,
must also consider the conditions under which what ought to happen frequently
does not.
We may call all philosophy empirical, so far as it is based on
grounds of experience: on the other band, that which delivers its doctrines from
a priori principles alone we may call pure philosophy. When the latter is merely
formal it is logic; if it is restricted to definite objects of the understanding
it is metaphysic.
In this way there arises the idea of a twofold metaphysic- a
metaphysic of nature and a metaphysic of morals. Physics will thus have an
empirical and also a rational part. It is the same with Ethics; but here the
empirical part might have the special name of practical anthropology, the name
morality being appropriated to the rational part.
All trades, arts, and handiworks have gained by division of
labour, namely, when, instead of one man doing everything, each confines himself
to a certain kind of work distinct from others in the treatment it requires, so
as to be able to perform it with greater facility and in the greatest
perfection. Where the different kinds of work are not distinguished and divided,
where everyone is a jack-of-all-trades, there manufactures remain still in the
greatest barbarism. It might deserve to be considered whether pure philosophy in
all its parts does not require a man specially devoted to it, and whether it
would not be better for the whole business of science if those who, to please
the tastes of the public, are wont to blend the rational and empirical elements
together, mixed in all sorts of proportions unknown to themselves, and who call
themselves independent thinkers, giving the name of minute philosophers to those
who apply themselves to the rational part only- if these, I say, were warned not
to carry on two employments together which differ widely in the treatment they
demand, for each of which perhaps a special talent is required, and the
combination of which in one person only produces bunglers. But I only ask here
whether the nature of science does not require that we should always carefully
separate the empirical from the rational part, and prefix to Physics proper (or
empirical physics) a metaphysic of nature, and to practical anthropology a
metaphysic of morals, which must be carefully cleared of everything empirical,
so that we may know how much can be accomplished by pure reason in both cases,
and from what sources it draws this its a priori teaching, and that whether the
latter inquiry is conducted by all moralists (whose name is legion), or only by
some who feel a calling thereto.
As my concern here is with moral philosophy, I limit the
question suggested to this: Whether it is not of the utmost necessity to
construct a pure thing which is only empirical and which belongs to
anthropology? for that such a philosophy must be possible is evident from the
common idea of duty and of the moral laws. Everyone must admit that if a law is
to have moral force, i.e., to be the basis of an obligation, it must carry with
it absolute necessity; that, for example, the precept, "Thou shalt not lie," is
not valid for men alone, as if other rational beings had no need to observe it;
and so with all the other moral laws properly so called; that, therefore, the
basis of obligation must not be sought in the nature of man, or in the
circumstances in the world in which he is placed, but a priori simply in the
conception of pure reason; and although any other precept which is founded on
principles of mere experience may be in certain respects universal, yet in as
far as it rests even in the least degree on an empirical basis, perhaps only as
to a motive, such a precept, while it may be a practical rule, can never be
called a moral law.
Thus not only are moral laws with their principles essentially
distinguished from every other kind of practical knowledge in which there is
anything empirical, but all moral philosophy rests wholly on its pure part. When
applied to man, it does not borrow the least thing from the knowledge of man
himself (anthropology), but gives laws a priori to him as a rational being. No
doubt these laws require a judgement sharpened by experience, in order on the
one hand to distinguish in what cases they are applicable, and on the other to
procure for them access to the will of the man and effectual influence on
conduct; since man is acted on by so many inclinations that, though capable of
the idea of a practical pure reason, he is not so easily able to make it
effective in concreto in his life.
A metaphysic of morals is therefore indispensably necessary, not
merely for speculative reasons, in order to investigate the sources of the
practical principles which are to be found a priori in our reason, but also
because morals themselves are liable to all sorts of corruption, as long as we
are without that clue and supreme canon by which to estimate them correctly. For
in order that an action should be morally good, it is not enough that it conform
to the moral law, but it must also be done for the sake of the law, otherwise
that conformity is only very contingent and uncertain; since a principle which
is not moral, although it may now and then produce actions conformable to the
law, will also often produce actions which contradict it. Now it is only a pure
philosophy that we can look for the moral law in its purity and genuineness
(and, in a practical matter, this is of the utmost consequence): we must,
therefore, begin with pure philosophy (metaphysic), and without it there cannot
be any moral philosophy at all. That which mingles these pure principles with
the empirical does not deserve the name of philosophy (for what distinguishes
philosophy from common rational knowledge is that it treats in separate sciences
what the latter only comprehends confusedly); much less does it deserve that of
moral philosophy, since by this confusion it even spoils the purity of morals
themselves, and counteracts its own end.
Let it not be thought, however, that what is here demanded is
already extant in the propaedeutic prefixed by the celebrated Wolf to his moral
philosophy, namely, his so-called general practical philosophy, and that,
therefore, we have not to strike into an entirely new field. Just because it was
to be a general practical philosophy, it has not taken into consideration a will
of any particular kind- say one which should be determined solely from a priori
principles without any empirical motives, and which we might call a pure will,
but volition in general, with all the actions and conditions which belong to it
in this general signification. By this it is distinguished from a metaphysic of
morals, just as general logic, which treats of the acts and canons of thought in
general, is distinguished from transcendental philosophy, which treats of the
particular acts and canons of pure thought, i.e., that whose cognitions are
altogether a priori. For the metaphysic of morals has to examine the idea and
the principles of a possible pure will, and not the acts and conditions of human
volition generally, which for the most part are drawn from psychology. It is
true that moral laws and duty are spoken of in the general moral philosophy
(contrary indeed to all fitness). But this is no objection, for in this respect
also the authors of that science remain true to their idea of it; they do not
distinguish the motives which are prescribed as such by reason alone altogether
a priori, and which are properly moral, from the empirical motives which the
understanding raises to general conceptions merely by comparison of experiences;
but, without noticing the difference of their sources, and looking on them all
as homogeneous, they consider only their greater or less amount. It is in this
way they frame their notion of obligation, which, though anything but moral, is
all that can be attained in a philosophy which passes no judgement at all on the
origin of all possible practical concepts, whether they are a priori, or only a
posteriori.
Intending to publish hereafter a metaphysic of morals, I issue
in the first instance these fundamental principles. Indeed there is properly no
other foundation for it than the critical examination of a pure practical
Reason; just as that of metaphysics is the critical examination of the pure
speculative reason, already published. But in the first place the former is not
so absolutely necessary as the latter, because in moral concerns human reason
can easily be brought to a high degree of correctness and completeness, even in
the commonest understanding, while on the contrary in its theoretic but pure use
it is wholly dialectical; and in the second place if the critique of a pure
practical reason is to be complete, it must be possible at the same time to show
its identity with the speculative reason in a common principle, for it can
ultimately be only one and the same reason which has to be distinguished merely
in its application. I could not, however, bring it to such completeness here,
without introducing considerations of a wholly different kind, which would be
perplexing to the reader. On this account I have adopted the title of
Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals instead of that of a Critical
Examination of the pure practical reason.
But in the third place, since a metaphysic of morals, in spite
of the discouraging title, is yet capable of being presented in popular form,
and one adapted to the common understanding, I find it useful to separate from
it this preliminary treatise on its fundamental principles, in order that I may
not hereafter have need to introduce these necessarily subtle discussions into a
book of a more simple character.
The present treatise is, however, nothing more than the
investigation and establishment of the supreme principle of morality, and this
alone constitutes a study complete in itself and one which ought to be kept
apart from every other moral investigation. No doubt my conclusions on this
weighty question, which has hitherto been very unsatisfactorily examined, would
receive much light from the application of the same principle to the whole
system, and would be greatly confirmed by the adequacy which it exhibits
throughout; but I must forego this advantage, which indeed would be after all
more gratifying than useful, since the easy applicability of a principle and its
apparent adequacy give no very certain proof of its soundness, but rather
inspire a certain partiality, which prevents us from examining and estimating it
strictly in itself and without regard to consequences.
I have adopted in this work the method which I think most
suitable, proceeding analytically from common knowledge to the determination of
its ultimate principle, and again descending synthetically from the examination
of this principle and its sources to the common knowledge in which we find it
employed. The division will, therefore, be as follows:
1 FIRST SECTION. Transition from the
common rational knowledge of morality to the philosophical.
2 SECOND SECTION. Transition from
popular moral philosophy to the metaphysic of morals.
3 THIRD SECTION. Final step from the
metaphysic of morals to the critique of the pure practical reason.
SEC_1
FIRST SECTION
TRANSITION FROM THE COMMON RATIONAL
KNOWLEDGE
OF MORALITY TO THE PHILOSOPHICAL
Nothing can possibly be conceived in the
world, or even out of it, which can be called good, without qualification,
except a good will. Intelligence, wit, judgement, and the other talents of the
mind, however they may be named, or courage, resolution, perseverance, as
qualities of temperament, are undoubtedly good and desirable in many respects;
but these gifts of nature may also become extremely bad and mischievous if the
will which is to make use of them, and which, therefore, constitutes what is
called character, is not good. It is the same with the gifts of fortune. Power,
riches, honour, even health, and the general well-being and contentment with
one's condition which is called happiness, inspire pride, and often presumption,
if there is not a good will to correct the influence of these on the mind, and
with this also to rectify the whole principle of acting and adapt it to its end.
The sight of a being who is not adorned with a single feature of a pure and good
will, enjoying unbroken prosperity, can never give pleasure to an impartial
rational spectator. Thus a good will appears to constitute the indispensable
condition even of being worthy of happiness.
There are even some qualities which are of service to this good
will itself and may facilitate its action, yet which have no intrinsic
unconditional value, but always presuppose a good will, and this qualifies the
esteem that we justly have for them and does not permit us to regard them as
absolutely good. Moderation in the affections and passions, self-control, and
calm deliberation are not only good in many respects, but even seem to
constitute part of the intrinsic worth of the person; but they are far from
deserving to be called good without qualification, although they have been so
unconditionally praised by the ancients. For without the principles of a good
will, they may become extremely bad, and the coolness of a villain not only
makes him far more dangerous, but also directly makes him more abominable in our
eyes than he would have been without it.
A good will is good not because of what it performs or effects,
not by its aptness for the attainment of some proposed end, but simply by virtue
of the volition; that is, it is good in itself, and considered by itself is to
be esteemed much higher than all that can be brought about by it in favour of
any inclination, nay even of the sum total of all inclinations. Even if it
should happen that, owing to special disfavour of fortune, or the niggardly
provision of a step-motherly nature, this will should wholly lack power to
accomplish its purpose, if with its greatest efforts it should yet achieve
nothing, and there should remain only the good will (not, to be sure, a mere
wish, but the summoning of all means in our power), then, like a jewel, it would
still shine by its own light, as a thing which has its whole value in itself.
Its usefulness or fruitlessness can neither add nor take away anything from this
value. It would be, as it were, only the setting to enable us to handle it the
more conveniently in common commerce, or to attract to it the attention of those
who are not yet connoisseurs, but not to recommend it to true connoisseurs, or
to determine its value.
There is, however, something so strange in this idea of the
absolute value of the mere will, in which no account is taken of its utility,
that notwithstanding the thorough assent of even common reason to the idea, yet
a suspicion must arise that it may perhaps really be the product of mere
high-flown fancy, and that we may have misunderstood the purpose of nature in
assigning reason as the governor of our will. Therefore we will examine this
idea from this point of view.
In the physical constitution of an organized being, that is, a
being adapted suitably to the purposes of life, we assume it as a fundamental
principle that no organ for any purpose will be found but what is also the
fittest and best adapted for that purpose. Now in a being which has reason and a
will, if the proper object of nature were its conservation, its welfare, in a
word, its happiness, then nature would have hit upon a very bad arrangement in
selecting the reason of the creature to carry out this purpose. For all the
actions which the creature has to perform with a view to this purpose, and the
whole rule of its conduct, would be far more surely prescribed to it by
instinct, and that end would have been attained thereby much more certainly than
it ever can be by reason. Should reason have been communicated to this favoured
creature over and above, it must only have served it to contemplate the happy
constitution of its nature, to admire it, to congratulate itself thereon, and to
feel thankful for it to the beneficent cause, but not that it should subject its
desires to that weak and delusive guidance and meddle bunglingly with the
purpose of nature. In a word, nature would have taken care that reason should
not break forth into practical exercise, nor have the presumption, with its weak
insight, to think out for itself the plan of happiness, and of the means of
attaining it. Nature would not only have taken on herself the choice of the
ends, but also of the means, and with wise foresight would have entrusted both
to instinct.
And, in fact, we find that the more a cultivated reason applies
itself with deliberate purpose to the enjoyment of life and happiness, so much
the more does the man fail of true satisfaction. And from this circumstance
there arises in many, if they are candid enough to confess it, a certain degree
of misology, that is, hatred of reason, especially in the case of those who are
most experienced in the use of it, because after calculating all the advantages
they derive, I do not say from the invention of all the arts of common luxury,
but even from the sciences (which seem to them to be after all only a luxury of
the understanding), they find that they have, in fact, only brought more trouble
on their shoulders, rather than gained in happiness; and they end by envying,
rather than despising, the more common stamp of men who keep closer to the
guidance of mere instinct and do not allow their reason much influence on their
conduct. And this we must admit, that the judgement of those who would very much
lower the lofty eulogies of the advantages which reason gives us in regard to
the happiness and satisfaction of life, or who would even reduce them below
zero, is by no means morose or ungrateful to the goodness with which the world
is governed, but that there lies at the root of these judgements the idea that
our existence has a different and far nobler end, for which, and not for
happiness, reason is properly intended, and which must, therefore, be regarded
as the supreme condition to which the private ends of man must, for the most
part, be postponed.
For as reason is not competent to guide the will with certainty
in regard to its objects and the satisfaction of all our wants (which it to some
extent even multiplies), this being an end to which an implanted instinct would
have led with much greater certainty; and since, nevertheless, reason is
imparted to us as a practical faculty, i.e., as one which is to have influence
on the will, therefore, admitting that nature generally in the distribution of
her capacities has adapted the means to the end, its true destination must be to
produce a will, not merely good as a means to something else, but good in
itself, for which reason was absolutely necessary. This will then, though not
indeed the sole and complete good, must be the supreme good and the condition of
every other, even of the desire of happiness. Under these circumstances, there
is nothing inconsistent with the wisdom of nature in the fact that the
cultivation of the reason, which is requisite for the first and unconditional
purpose, does in many ways interfere, at least in this life, with the attainment
of the second, which is always conditional, namely, happiness. Nay, it may even
reduce it to nothing, without nature thereby failing of her purpose. For reason
recognizes the establishment of a good will as its highest practical
destination, and in attaining this purpose is capable only of a satisfaction of
its own proper kind, namely that from the attainment of an end, which end again
is determined by reason only, notwithstanding that this may involve many a
disappointment to the ends of inclination.
We have then to develop the notion of a will which deserves to
be highly esteemed for itself and is good without a view to anything further, a
notion which exists already in the sound natural understanding, requiring rather
to be cleared up than to be taught, and which in estimating the value of our
actions always takes the first place and constitutes the condition of all the
rest. In order to do this, we will take the notion of duty, which includes that
of a good will, although implying certain subjective restrictions and
hindrances. These, however, far from concealing it, or rendering it
unrecognizable, rather bring it out by contrast and make it shine forth so much
the brighter.
I omit here all actions which are already recognized as
inconsistent with duty, although they may be useful for this or that purpose,
for with these the question whether they are done from duty cannot arise at all,
since they even conflict with it. I also set aside those actions which really
conform to duty, but to which men have no direct inclination, performing them
because they are impelled thereto by some other inclination. For in this case we
can readily distinguish whether the action which agrees with duty is done from
duty, or from a selfish view. It is much harder to make this distinction when
the action accords with duty and the subject has besides a direct inclination to
it. For example, it is always a matter of duty that a dealer should not over
charge an inexperienced purchaser; and wherever there is much commerce the
prudent tradesman does not overcharge, but keeps a fixed price for everyone, so
that a child buys of him as well as any other. Men are thus honestly served; but
this is not enough to make us believe that the tradesman has so acted from duty
and from principles of honesty: his own advantage required it; it is out of the
question in this case to suppose that he might besides have a direct inclination
in favour of the buyers, so that, as it were, from love he should give no
advantage to one over another. Accordingly the action was done neither from duty
nor from direct inclination, but merely with a selfish view.
On the other hand, it is a duty to maintain one's life; and, in
addition, everyone has also a direct inclination to do so. But on this account
the of anxious care which most men take for it has no intrinsic worth, and their
maxim has no moral import. They preserve their life as duty requires, no doubt,
but not because duty requires. On the other band, if adversity and hopeless
sorrow have completely taken away the relish for life; if the unfortunate one,
strong in mind, indignant at his fate rather than desponding or dejected, wishes
for death, and yet preserves his life without loving it- not from inclination or
fear, but from duty- then his maxim has a moral worth.
To be beneficent when we can is a duty; and besides this, there
are many minds so sympathetically constituted that, without any other motive of
vanity or self-interest, they find a pleasure in spreading joy around them and
can take delight in the satisfaction of others so far as it is their own work.
But I maintain that in such a case an action of this kind, however proper,
however amiable it may be, has nevertheless no true moral worth, but is on a
level with other inclinations, e.g., the inclination to honour, which, if it is
happily directed to that which is in fact of public utility and accordant with
duty and consequently honourable, deserves praise and encouragement, but not
esteem. For the maxim lacks the moral import, namely, that such actions be done
from duty, not from inclination. Put the case that the mind of that
philanthropist were clouded by sorrow of his own, extinguishing all sympathy
with the lot of others, and that, while he still has the power to benefit others
in distress, he is not touched by their trouble because he is absorbed with his
own; and now suppose that he tears himself out of this dead insensibility, and
performs the action without any inclination to it, but simply from duty, then
first has his action its genuine moral worth. Further still; if nature has put
little sympathy in the heart of this or that man; if he, supposed to be an
upright man, is by temperament cold and indifferent to the sufferings of others,
perhaps because in respect of his own he is provided with the special gift of
patience and fortitude and supposes, or even requires, that others should have
the same- and such a man would certainly not be the meanest product of nature-
but if nature had not specially framed him for a philanthropist, would he not
still find in himself a source from whence to give himself a far higher worth
than that of a good-natured temperament could be? Unquestionably. It is just in
this that the moral worth of the character is brought out which is incomparably
the highest of all, namely, that he is beneficent, not from inclination, but
from duty.
To secure one's own happiness is a duty, at least indirectly;
for discontent with one's condition, under a pressure of many anxieties and
amidst unsatisfied wants, might easily become a great temptation to
transgression of duty. But here again, without looking to duty, all men have
already the strongest and most intimate inclination to happiness, because it is
just in this idea that all inclinations are combined in one total. But the
precept of happiness is often of such a sort that it greatly interferes with
some inclinations, and yet a man cannot form any definite and certain conception
of the sum of satisfaction of all of them which is called happiness. It is not
then to be wondered at that a single inclination, definite both as to what it
promises and as to the time within which it can be gratified, is often able to
overcome such a fluctuating idea, and that a gouty patient, for instance, can
choose to enjoy what he likes, and to suffer what he may, since, according to
his calculation, on this occasion at least, he has not sacrificed the enjoyment
of the present moment to a possibly mistaken expectation of a happiness which is
supposed to be found in health. But even in this case, if the general desire for
happiness did not influence his will, and supposing that in his particular case
health was not a necessary element in this calculation, there yet remains in
this, as in all other cases, this law, namely, that he should promote his
happiness not from inclination but from duty, and by this would his conduct
first acquire true moral worth.
It is in this manner, undoubtedly, that we are to understand
those passages of Scripture also in which we are commanded to love our
neighbour, even our enemy. For love, as an affection, cannot be commanded, but
beneficence for duty's sake may; even though we are not impelled to it by any
inclination- nay, are even repelled by a natural and unconquerable aversion.
This is practical love and not pathological- a love which is seated in the will,
and not in the propensions of sense- in principles of action and not of tender
sympathy; and it is this love alone which can be commanded.
The second proposition is: That an action done from duty derives
its moral worth, not from the purpose which is to be attained by it, but from
the maxim by which it is determined, and therefore does not depend on the
realization of the object of the action, but merely on the principle of volition
by which the action has taken place, without regard to any object of desire. It
is clear from what precedes that the purposes which we may have in view in our
actions, or their effects regarded as ends and springs of the will, cannot give
to actions any unconditional or moral worth. In what, then, can their worth lie,
if it is not to consist in the will and in reference to its expected effect? It
cannot lie anywhere but in the principle of the will without regard to the ends
which can be attained by the action. For the will stands between its a priori
principle, which is formal, and its a posteriori spring, which is material, as
between two roads, and as it must be determined by something, it that it must be
determined by the formal principle of volition when an action is done from duty,
in which case every material principle has been withdrawn from it.
The third proposition, which is a consequence of the two
preceding, I would express thus Duty is the necessity of acting from respect for
the law. I may have inclination for an object as the effect of my proposed
action, but I cannot have respect for it, just for this reason, that it is an
effect and not an energy of will. Similarly I cannot have respect for
inclination, whether my own or another's; I can at most, if my own, approve it;
if another's, sometimes even love it; i.e., look on it as favourable to my own
interest. It is only what is connected with my will as a principle, by no means
as an effect- what does not subserve my inclination, but overpowers it, or at
least in case of choice excludes it from its calculation- in other words, simply
the law of itself, which can be an object of respect, and hence a command. Now
an action done from duty must wholly exclude the influence of inclination and
with it every object of the will, so that nothing remains which can determine
the will except objectively the law, and subjectively pure respect for this
practical law, and consequently the maxim * that I should follow this law even
to the thwarting of all my inclinations.
* A maxim is the subjective principle of
volition. The objective principle (i.e., that which would also serve
subjectively as a practical principle to all rational beings if reason had full
power over the faculty of desire) is the practical law.
Thus the moral worth of an action does
not lie in the effect expected from it, nor in any principle of action which
requires to borrow its motive from this expected effect. For all these effects-
agreeableness of one's condition and even the promotion of the happiness of
others- could have been also brought about by other causes, so that for this
there would have been no need of the will of a rational being; whereas it is in
this alone that the supreme and unconditional good can be found. The pre-eminent
good which we call moral can therefore consist in nothing else than the
conception of law in itself, which certainly is only possible in a rational
being, in so far as this conception, and not the expected effect, determines the
will. This is a good which is already present in the person who acts
accordingly, and we have not to wait for it to appear first in the result. *
* It might be here objected to me that I
take refuge behind the word respect in an obscure feeling, instead of giving a
distinct solution of the question by a concept of the reason. But although
respect is a feeling, it is not a feeling received through influence, but is
self-wrought by a rational concept, and, therefore, is specifically distinct
from all feelings of the former kind, which may be referred either to
inclination or fear, What I recognise immediately as a law for me, I recognise
with respect. This merely signifies the consciousness that my will is
subordinate to a law, without the intervention of other influences on my sense.
The immediate determination of the will by the law, and the consciousness of
this, is called respect, so that this is regarded as an effect of the law on the
subject, and not as the cause of it. Respect is properly the conception of a
worth which thwarts my self-love. Accordingly it is something which is
considered neither as an object of inclination nor of fear, although it has
something analogous to both. The object of respect is the law only, and that the
law which we impose on ourselves and yet recognise as necessary in itself. As a
law, we are subjected too it without consulting self-love; as imposed by us on
ourselves, it is a result of our will. In the former aspect it has an analogy to
fear, in the latter to inclination. Respect for a person is properly only
respect for the law (of honesty, etc.) of which he gives us an example. Since we
also look on the improvement of our talents as a duty, we consider that we see
in a person of talents, as it were, the example of a law (viz., to become like
him in this by exercise), and this constitutes our respect. All so-called moral
interest consists simply in respect for the law.
But what sort of law can that be, the
conception of which must determine the will, even without paying any regard to
the effect expected from it, in order that this will may be called good
absolutely and without qualification? As I have deprived the will of every
impulse which could arise to it from obedience to any law, there remains nothing
but the universal conformity of its actions to law in general, which alone is to
serve the will as a principle, i.e., I am never to act otherwise than so that I
could also will that my maxim should become a universal law. Here, now, it is
the simple conformity to law in general, without assuming any particular law
applicable to certain actions, that serves the will as its principle and must so
serve it, if duty is not to be a vain delusion and a chimerical notion. The
common reason of men in its practical judgements perfectly coincides with this
and always has in view the principle here suggested. Let the question be, for
example: May I when in distress make a promise with the intention not to keep
it? I readily distinguish here between the two significations which the question
may have: Whether it is prudent, or whether it is right, to make a false
promise? The former may undoubtedly of be the case. I see clearly indeed that it
is not enough to extricate myself from a present difficulty by means of this
subterfuge, but it must be well considered whether there may not hereafter
spring from this lie much greater inconvenience than that from which I now free
myself, and as, with all my supposed cunning, the consequences cannot be so
easily foreseen but that credit once lost may be much more injurious to me than
any mischief which I seek to avoid at present, it should be considered whether
it would not be more prudent to act herein according to a universal maxim and to
make it a habit to promise nothing except with the intention of keeping it. But
it is soon clear to me that such a maxim will still only be based on the fear of
consequences. Now it is a wholly different thing to be truthful from duty and to
be so from apprehension of injurious consequences. In the first case, the very
notion of the action already implies a law for me; in the second case, I must
first look about elsewhere to see what results may be combined with it which
would affect myself. For to deviate from the principle of duty is beyond all
doubt wicked; but to be unfaithful to my maxim of prudence may often be very
advantageous to me, although to abide by it is certainly safer. The shortest
way, however, and an unerring one, to discover the answer to this question
whether a lying promise is consistent with duty, is to ask myself, "Should I be
content that my maxim (to extricate myself from difficulty by a false promise)
should hold good as a universal law, for myself as well as for others?" and
should I be able to say to myself, "Every one may make a deceitful promise when
he finds himself in a difficulty from which he cannot otherwise extricate
himself?" Then I presently become aware that while I can will the lie, I can by
no means will that lying should be a universal law. For with such a law there
would be no promises at all, since it would be in vain to allege my intention in
regard to my future actions to those who would not believe this allegation, or
if they over hastily did so would pay me back in my own coin. Hence my maxim, as
soon as it should be made a universal law, would necessarily destroy itself.
I do not, therefore, need any far-reaching penetration to
discern what I have to do in order that my will may be morally good.
Inexperienced in the course of the world, incapable of being prepared for all
its contingencies, I only ask myself: Canst thou also will that thy maxim should
be a universal law? If not, then it must be rejected, and that not because of a
disadvantage accruing from it to myself or even to others, but because it cannot
enter as a principle into a possible universal legislation, and reason extorts
from me immediate respect for such legislation. I do not indeed as yet discern
on what this respect is based (this the philosopher may inquire), but at least I
understand this, that it is an estimation of the worth which far outweighs all
worth of what is recommended by inclination, and that the necessity of acting
from pure respect for the practical law is what constitutes duty, to which every
other motive must give place, because it is the condition of a will being good
in itself, and the worth of such a will is above everything.
Thus, then, without quitting the moral knowledge of common human
reason, we have arrived at its principle. And although, no doubt, common men do
not conceive it in such an abstract and universal form, yet they always have it
really before their eyes and use it as the standard of their decision. Here it
would be easy to show how, with this compass in hand, men are well able to
distinguish, in every case that occurs, what is good, what bad, conformably to
duty or inconsistent with it, if, without in the least teaching them anything
new, we only, like Socrates, direct their attention to the principle they
themselves employ; and that, therefore, we do not need science and philosophy to
know what we should do to be honest and good, yea, even wise and virtuous.
Indeed we might well have conjectured beforehand that the knowledge of what
every man is bound to do, and therefore also to know, would be within the reach
of every man, even the commonest. Here we cannot forbear admiration when we see
how great an advantage the practical judgement has over the theoretical in the
common understanding of men. In the latter, if common reason ventures to depart
from the laws of experience and from the perceptions of the senses, it falls
into mere inconceivabilities and self-contradictions, at least into a chaos of
uncertainty, obscurity, and instability. But in the practical sphere it is just
when the common understanding excludes all sensible springs from practical laws
that its power of judgement begins to show itself to advantage. It then becomes
even subtle, whether it be that it chicanes with its own conscience or with
other claims respecting what is to be called right, or whether it desires for
its own instruction to determine honestly the worth of actions; and, in the
latter case, it may even have as good a hope of hitting the mark as any
philosopher whatever can promise himself. Nay, it is almost more sure of doing
so, because the philosopher cannot have any other principle, while he may easily
perplex his judgement by a multitude of considerations foreign to the matter,
and so turn aside from the right way. Would it not therefore be wiser in moral
concerns to acquiesce in the judgement of common reason, or at most only to call
in philosophy for the purpose of rendering the system of morals more complete
and intelligible, and its rules more convenient for use (especially for
disputation), but not so as to draw off the common understanding from its happy
simplicity, or to bring it by means of philosophy into a new path of inquiry and
instruction?
Innocence is indeed a glorious thing; only, on the other hand,
it is very sad that it cannot well maintain itself and is easily seduced. On
this account even wisdom- which otherwise consists more in conduct than in
knowledge- yet has need of science, not in order to learn from it, but to secure
for its precepts admission and permanence. Against all the commands of duty
which reason represents to man as so deserving of respect, he feels in himself a
powerful counterpoise in his wants and inclinations, the entire satisfaction of
which he sums up under the name of happiness. Now reason issues its commands
unyieldingly, without promising anything to the inclinations, and, as it were,
with disregard and contempt for these claims, which are so impetuous, and at the
same time so plausible, and which will not allow themselves to be suppressed by
any command. Hence there arises a natural dialectic, i.e., a disposition, to
argue against these strict laws of duty and to question their validity, or at
least their purity and strictness; and, if possible, to make them more accordant
with our wishes and inclinations, that is to say, to corrupt them at their very
source, and entirely to destroy their worth- a thing which even common practical
reason cannot ultimately call good.
Thus is the common reason of man compelled to go out of its
sphere, and to take a step into the field of a practical philosophy, not to
satisfy any speculative want (which never occurs to it as long as it is content
to be mere sound reason), but even on practical grounds, in order to attain in
it information and clear instruction respecting the source of its principle, and
the correct determination of it in opposition to the maxims which are based on
wants and inclinations, so that it may escape from the perplexity of opposite
claims and not run the risk of losing all genuine moral principles through the
equivocation into which it easily falls. Thus, when practical reason cultivates
itself, there insensibly arises in it a dialetic which forces it to seek aid in
philosophy, just as happens to it in its theoretic use; and in this case,
therefore, as well as in the other, it will find rest nowhere but in a thorough
critical examination of our reason.
SEC_2
SECOND SECTION
TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL
PHILOSOPHY
TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS
If we have hitherto drawn our notion of
duty from the common use of our practical reason, it is by no means to be
inferred that we have treated it as an empirical notion. On the contrary, if we
attend to the experience of men's conduct, we meet frequent and, as we ourselves
allow, just complaints that one cannot find a single certain example of the
disposition to act from pure duty. Although many things are done in conformity
with what duty prescribes, it is nevertheless always doubtful whether they are
done strictly from duty, so as to have a moral worth. Hence there have at all
times been philosophers who have altogether denied that this disposition
actually exists at all in human actions, and have ascribed everything to a more
or less refined self-love. Not that they have on that account questioned the
soundness of the conception of morality; on the contrary, they spoke with
sincere regret of the frailty and corruption of human nature, which, though
noble enough to take its rule an idea so worthy of respect, is yet weak to
follow it and employs reason which ought to give it the law only for the purpose
of providing for the interest of the inclinations, whether singly or at the best
in the greatest possible harmony with one another.
In fact, it is absolutely impossible to make out by experience
with complete certainty a single case in which the maxim of an action, however
right in itself, rested simply on moral grounds and on the conception of duty.
Sometimes it happens that with the sharpest self-examination we can find nothing
beside the moral principle of duty which could have been powerful enough to move
us to this or that action and to so great a sacrifice; yet we cannot from this
infer with certainty that it was not really some secret impulse of self-love,
under the false appearance of duty, that was the actual determining cause of the
will. We like them to flatter ourselves by falsely taking credit for a more
noble motive; whereas in fact we can never, even by the strictest examination,
get completely behind the secret springs of action; since, when the question is
of moral worth, it is not with the actions which we see that we are concerned,
but with those inward principles of them which we do not see.
Moreover, we cannot better serve the wishes of those who
ridicule all morality as a mere chimera of human imagination over stepping
itself from vanity, than by conceding to them that notions of duty must be drawn
only from experience (as from indolence, people are ready to think is also the
case with all other notions); for or is to prepare for them a certain triumph. I
am willing to admit out of love of humanity that even most of our actions are
correct, but if we look closer at them we everywhere come upon the dear self
which is always prominent, and it is this they have in view and not the strict
command of duty which would often require self-denial. Without being an enemy of
virtue, a cool observer, one that does not mistake the wish for good, however
lively, for its reality, may sometimes doubt whether true virtue is actually
found anywhere in the world, and this especially as years increase and the
judgement is partly made wiser by experience and partly, also, more acute in
observation. This being so, nothing can secure us from falling away altogether
from our ideas of duty, or maintain in the soul a well-grounded respect for its
law, but the clear conviction that although there should never have been actions
which really sprang from such pure sources, yet whether this or that takes place
is not at all the question; but that reason of itself, independent on all
experience, ordains what ought to take place, that accordingly actions of which
perhaps the world has hitherto never given an example, the feasibility even of
which might be very much doubted by one who founds everything on experience, are
nevertheless inflexibly commanded by reason; that, e.g., even though there might
never yet have been a sincere friend, yet not a whit the less is pure sincerity
in friendship required of every man, because, prior to all experience, this duty
is involved as duty in the idea of a reason determining the will by a priori
principles.
When we add further that, unless we deny that the notion of
morality has any truth or reference to any possible object, we must admit that
its law must be valid, not merely for men but for all rational creatures
generally, not merely under certain contingent conditions or with exceptions but
with absolute necessity, then it is clear that no experience could enable us to
infer even the possibility of such apodeictic laws. For with what right could we
bring into unbounded respect as a universal precept for every rational nature
that which perhaps holds only under the contingent conditions of humanity? Or
how could laws of the determination of our will be regarded as laws of the
determination of the will of rational beings generally, and for us only as such,
if they were merely empirical and did not take their origin wholly a priori from
pure but practical reason?
Nor could anything be more fatal to morality than that we should
wish to derive it from examples. For every example of it that is set before me
must be first itself tested by principles of morality, whether it is worthy to
serve as an original example, i.e., as a pattern; but by no means can it
authoritatively furnish the conception of morality. Even the Holy One of the
Gospels must first be compared with our ideal of moral perfection before we can
recognise Him as such; and so He says of Himself, "Why call ye Me (whom you see)
good; none is good (the model of good) but God only (whom ye do not see)?" But
whence have we the conception of God as the supreme good? Simply from the idea
of moral perfection, which reason frames a priori and connects inseparably with
the notion of a free will. Imitation finds no place at all in morality, and
examples serve only for encouragement, i.e., they put beyond doubt the
feasibility of what the law commands, they make visible that which the practical
rule expresses more generally, but they can never authorize us to set aside the
true original which lies in reason and to guide ourselves by examples.
If then there is no genuine supreme principle of morality but
what must rest simply on pure reason, independent of all experience, I think it
is not necessary even to put the question whether it is good to exhibit these
concepts in their generality (in abstracto) as they are established a priori
along with the principles belonging to them, if our knowledge is to be
distinguished from the vulgar and to be called philosophical.
In our times indeed this might perhaps be necessary; for if we
collected votes whether pure rational knowledge separated from everything
empirical, that is to say, metaphysic of morals, or whether popular practical
philosophy is to be preferred, it is easy to guess which side would
preponderate.
This descending to popular notions is certainly very
commendable, if the ascent to the principles of pure reason has first taken
place and been satisfactorily accomplished. This implies that we first found
ethics on metaphysics, and then, when it is firmly established, procure a
hearing for it by giving it a popular character. But it is quite absurd to try
to be popular in the first inquiry, on which the soundness of the principles
depends. It is not only that this proceeding can never lay claim to the very
rare merit of a true philosophical popularity, since there is no art in being
intelligible if one renounces all thoroughness of insight; but also it produces
a disgusting medley of compiled observations and half-reasoned principles.
Shallow pates enjoy this because it can be used for every-day chat, but the
sagacious find in it only confusion, and being unsatisfied and unable to help
themselves, they turn away their eyes, while philosophers, who see quite well
through this delusion, are little listened to when they call men off for a time
from this pretended popularity, in order that they might be rightfully popular
after they have attained a definite insight.
We need only look at the attempts of moralists in that favourite
fashion, and we shall find at one time the special constitution of human nature
(including, however, the idea of a rational nature generally), at one time
perfection, at another happiness, here moral sense, there fear of God. a little
of this, and a little of that, in marvellous mixture, without its occurring to
them to ask whether the principles of morality are to be sought in the knowledge
of human nature at all (which we can have only from experience); or, if this is
not so, if these principles are to be found altogether a priori, free from
everything empirical, in pure rational concepts only and nowhere else, not even
in the smallest degree; then rather to adopt the method of making this a
separate inquiry, as pure practical philosophy, or (if one may use a name so
decried) as metaphysic of morals, * to bring it by itself to completeness, and
to require the public, which wishes for popular treatment, to await the issue of
this undertaking.
* Just as pure mathematics are
distinguished from applied, pure logic from applied, so if we choose we may also
distinguish pure philosophy of morals (metaphysic) from applied (viz., applied
to human nature). By this designation we are also at once reminded that moral
principles are not based on properties of human nature, but must subsist a
priori of themselves, while from such principles practical rules must be capable
of being deduced for every rational nature, and accordingly for that of man.
Such a metaphysic of morals, completely
isolated, not mixed with any anthropology, theology, physics, or hyperphysics,
and still less with occult qualities (which we might call hypophysical), is not
only an indispensable substratum of all sound theoretical knowledge of duties,
but is at the same time a desideratum of the highest importance to the actual
fulfilment of their precepts. For the pure conception of duty, unmixed with any
foreign addition of empirical attractions, and, in a word, the conception of the
moral law, exercises on the human heart, by way of reason alone (which first
becomes aware with this that it can of itself be practical), an influence so
much more powerful than all other springs * which may be derived from the field
of experience, that, in the consciousness of its worth, it despises the latter,
and can by degrees become their master; whereas a mixed ethics, compounded
partly of motives drawn from feelings and inclinations, and partly also of
conceptions of reason, must make the mind waver between motives which cannot be
brought under any principle, which lead to good only by mere accident and very
often also to evil.
* I have a letter from the late
excellent Sulzer, in which he asks me what can be the reason that moral
instruction, although containing much that is convincing for the reason, yet
accomplishes so little? My answer was postponed in order that I might make it
complete. But it is simply this: that the teachers themselves have not got their
own notions clear, and when they endeavour to make up for this by raking up
motives of moral goodness from every quarter, trying to make their physic right
strong, they spoil it. For the commonest understanding shows that if we imagine,
on the one hand, an act of honesty done with steadfast mind, apart from every
view to advantage of any kind in this world or another, and even under the
greatest temptations of necessity or allurement, and, on the other hand, a
similar act which was affected, in however low a degree, by a foreign motive,
the former leaves far behind and eclipses the second; it elevates the soul and
inspires the wish to be able to act in like manner oneself. Even moderately
young children feel this impression, ana one should never represent duties to
them in any other light.
From what has been said, it is clear
that all moral conceptions have their seat and origin completely a priori in the
reason, and that, moreover, in the commonest reason just as truly as in that
which is in the highest degree speculative; that they cannot be obtained by
abstraction from any empirical, and therefore merely contingent, knowledge; that
it is just this purity of their origin that makes them worthy to serve as our
supreme practical principle, and that just in proportion as we add anything
empirical, we detract from their genuine influence and from the absolute value
of actions; that it is not only of the greatest necessity, in a purely
speculative point of view, but is also of the greatest practical importance, to
derive these notions and laws from pure reason, to present them pure and
unmixed, and even to determine the compass of this practical or pure rational
knowledge, i.e., to determine the whole faculty of pure practical reason; and,
in doing so, we must not make its principles dependent on the particular nature
of human reason, though in speculative philosophy this may be permitted, or may
even at times be necessary; but since moral laws ought to hold good for every
rational creature, we must derive them from the general concept of a rational
being. In this way, although for its application to man morality has need of
anthropology, yet, in the first instance, we must treat it independently as pure
philosophy, i.e., as metaphysic, complete in itself (a thing which in such
distinct branches of science is easily done); knowing well that unless we are in
possession of this, it would not only be vain to determine the moral element of
duty in right actions for purposes of speculative criticism, but it would be
impossible to base morals on their genuine principles, even for common practical
purposes, especially of moral instruction, so as to produce pure moral
dispositions, and to engraft them on men's minds to the promotion of the
greatest possible good in the world.
But in order that in this study we may not merely advance by the
natural steps from the common moral judgement (in this case very worthy of
respect) to the philosophical, as has been already done, but also from a popular
philosophy, which goes no further than it can reach by groping with the help of
examples, to metaphysic (which does allow itself to be checked by anything
empirical and, as it must measure the whole extent of this kind of rational
knowledge, goes as far as ideal conceptions, where even examples fail us), we
must follow and clearly describe the practical faculty of reason, from the
general rules of its determination to the point where the notion of duty springs
from it.
Everything in nature works according to laws. Rational beings
alone have the faculty of acting according to the conception of laws, that is
according to principles, i.e., have a will. Since the deduction of actions from
principles requires reason, the will is nothing but practical reason. If reason
infallibly determines the will, then the actions of such a being which are
recognised as objectively necessary are subjectively necessary also, i.e., the
will is a faculty to choose that only which reason independent of inclination
recognises as practically necessary, i.e., as good. But if reason of itself does
not sufficiently determine the will, if the latter is subject also to subjective
conditions (particular impulses) which do not always coincide with the objective
conditions; in a word, if the will does not in itself completely accord with
reason (which is actually the case with men), then the actions which objectively
are recognised as necessary are subjectively contingent, and the determination
of such a will according to objective laws is obligation, that is to say, the
relation of the objective laws to a will that is not thoroughly good is
conceived as the determination of the will of a rational being by principles of
reason, but which the will from its nature does not of necessity follow.
The conception of an objective principle, in so far as it is
obligatory for a will, is called a command (of reason), and the formula of the
command is called an imperative.
All imperatives are expressed by the word ought [or shall], and
thereby indicate the relation of an objective law of reason to a will, which
from its subjective constitution is not necessarily determined by it (an
obligation). They say that something would be good to do or to forbear, but they
say it to a will which does not always do a thing because it is conceived to be
good to do it. That is practically good, however, which determines the will by
means of the conceptions of reason, and consequently not from subjective causes,
but objectively, that is on principles which are valid for every rational being
as such. It is distinguished from the pleasant, as that which influences the
will only by means of sensation from merely subjective causes, valid only for
the sense of this or that one, and not as a principle of reason, which holds for
every one. *
* The dependence of the desires on
sensations is called inclination, and this accordingly always indicates a want.
The dependence of a contingently determinable will on principles of reason is
called an interest. This therefore, is found only in the case of a dependent
will which does not always of itself conform to reason; in the Divine will we
cannot conceive any interest. But the human will can also take an interest in a
thing without therefore acting from interest. The former signifies the practical
interest in the action, the latter the pathological in the object of the action.
The former indicates only dependence of the will on principles of reason in
themselves; the second, dependence on principles of reason for the sake of
inclination, reason supplying only the practical rules how the requirement of
the inclination may be satisfied. In the first case the action interests me; in
the second the object of the action (because it is pleasant to me). We have seen
in the first section that in an action done from duty we must look not to the
interest in the object, but only to that in the action itself, and in its
rational principle (viz., the law).
A perfectly good will would therefore be
equally subject to objective laws (viz., laws of good), but could not be
conceived as obliged thereby to act lawfully, because of itself from its
subjective constitution it can only be determined by the conception of good.
Therefore no imperatives hold for the Divine will, or in general for a holy
will; ought is here out of place, because the volition is already of itself
necessarily in unison with the law. Therefore imperatives are only formulae to
express the relation of objective laws of all volition to the subjective
imperfection of the will of this or that rational being, e.g., the human will.
Now all imperatives command either hypothetically or
categorically. The former represent the practical necessity of a possible action
as means to something else that is willed (or at least which one might possibly
will). The categorical imperative would be that which represented an action as
necessary of itself without reference to another end, i.e., as objectively
necessary.
Since every practical law represents a possible action as good
and, on this account, for a subject who is practically determinable by reason,
necessary, all imperatives are formulae determining an action which is necessary
according to the principle of a will good in some respects. If now the action is
good only as a means to something else, then the imperative is hypothetical; if
it is conceived as good in itself and consequently as being necessarily the
principle of a will which of itself conforms to reason, then it is categorical.
Thus the imperative declares what action possible by me would be
good and presents the practical rule in relation to a will which does not
forthwith perform an action simply because it is good, whether because the
subject does not always know that it is good, or because, even if it know this,
yet its maxims might be opposed to the objective principles of practical reason.
Accordingly the hypothetical imperative only says that the
action is good for some purpose, possible or actual. In the first case it is a
problematical, in the second an assertorial practical principle. The categorical
imperative which declares an action to be objectively necessary in itself
without reference to any purpose, i.e., without any other end, is valid as an
apodeictic (practical) principle.
Whatever is possible only by the power of some rational being
may also be conceived as a possible purpose of some will; and therefore the
principles of action as regards the means necessary to attain some possible
purpose are in fact infinitely numerous. All sciences have a practical part,
consisting of problems expressing that some end is possible for us and of
imperatives directing how it may be attained. These may, therefore, be called in
general imperatives of skill. Here there is no question whether the end is
rational and good, but only what one must do in order to attain it. The precepts
for the physician to make his patient thoroughly healthy, and for a poisoner to
ensure certain death, are of equal value in this respect, that each serves to
effect its purpose perfectly. Since in early youth it cannot be known what ends
are likely to occur to us in the course of life, parents seek to have their
children taught a great many things, and provide for their skill in the use of
means for all sorts of arbitrary ends, of none of which can they determine
whether it may not perhaps hereafter be an object to their pupil, but which it
is at all events possible that he might aim at; and this anxiety is so great
that they commonly neglect to form and correct their judgement on the value of
the things which may be chosen as ends.
There is one end, however, which may be assumed to be actually
such to all rational beings (so far as imperatives apply to them, viz., as
dependent beings), and, therefore, one purpose which they not merely may have,
but which we may with certainty assume that they all actually have by a natural
necessity, and this is happiness. The hypothetical imperative which expresses
the practical necessity of an action as means to the advancement of happiness is
assertorial. We are not to present it as necessary for an uncertain and merely
possible purpose, but for a purpose which we may presuppose with certainty and a
priori in every man, because it belongs to his being. Now skill in the choice of
means to his own greatest well-being may be called prudence, * in the narrowest
sense. And thus the imperative which refers to the choice of means to one's own
happiness, i.e., the precept of prudence, is still always hypothetical; the
action is not commanded absolutely, but only as means to another purpose.
* The word prudence is taken in two
senses: in the one it may bear the name of knowledge of the world, in the other
that of private prudence. The former is a man's ability to influence others so
as to use them for his own purposes. The latter is the sagacity to combine all
these purposes for his own lasting benefit. This latter is properly that to
which the value even of the former is reduced, and when a man is prudent in the
former sense, but not in the latter, we might better say of him that he is
clever and cunning, but, on the whole, imprudent.
Finally, there is an imperative which
commands a certain conduct immediately, without having as its condition any
other purpose to be attained by it. This imperative is categorical. It concerns
not the matter of the action, or its intended result, but its form and the
principle of which it is itself a result; and what is essentially good in it
consists in the mental disposition, let the consequence be what it may. This
imperative may be called that of morality.
There is a marked distinction also between the volitions on
these three sorts of principles in the dissimilarity of the obligation of the
will. In order to mark this difference more clearly, I think they would be most
suitably named in their order if we said they are either rules of skill, or
counsels of prudence, or commands (laws) of morality. For it is law only that
involves the conception of an unconditional and objective necessity, which is
consequently universally valid; and commands are laws which must be obeyed, that
is, must be followed, even in opposition to inclination. Counsels, indeed,
involve necessity, but one which can only hold under a contingent subjective
condition, viz., they depend on whether this or that man reckons this or that as
part of his happiness; the categorical imperative, on the contrary, is not
limited by any condition, and as being absolutely, although practically,
necessary, may be quite properly called a command. We might also call the first
kind of imperatives technical (belonging to art), the second pragmatic * (to
welfare), the third moral (belonging to free conduct generally, that is, to
morals).
* It seems to me that the proper
signification of the word pragmatic may be most accurately defined in this way.
For sanctions are called pragmatic which flow properly not from the law of the
states as necessary enactments, but from precaution for the general welfare. A
history is composed pragmatically when it teaches prudence, i.e., instructs the
world how it can provide for its interests better, or at least as well as, the
men of former time.
Now arises the question, how are all
these imperatives possible? This question does not seek to know how we can
conceive the accomplishment of the action which the imperative ordains, but
merely how we can conceive the obligation of the will which the imperative
expresses. No special explanation is needed to show how an imperative of skill
is possible. Whoever wills the end, wills also (so far as reason decides his
conduct) the means in his power which are indispensably necessary thereto. This
proposition is, as regards the volition, analytical; for, in willing an object
as my effect, there is already thought the causality of myself as an acting
cause, that is to say, the use of the means; and the imperative educes from the
conception of volition of an end the conception of actions necessary to this
end. Synthetical propositions must no doubt be employed in defining the means to
a proposed end; but they do not concern the principle, the act of the will, but
the object and its realization. E.g., that in order to bisect a line on an
unerring principle I must draw from its extremities two intersecting arcs; this
no doubt is taught by mathematics only in synthetical propositions; but if I
know that it is only by this process that the intended operation can be
performed, then to say that, if I fully will the operation, I also will the
action required for it, is an analytical proposition; for it is one and the same
thing to conceive something as an effect which I can produce in a certain way,
and to conceive myself as acting in this way.
If it were only equally easy to give a definite conception of
happiness, the imperatives of prudence would correspond exactly with those of
skill, and would likewise be analytical. For in this case as in that, it could
be said: "Whoever wills the end, wills also (according to the dictate of reason
necessarily) the indispensable means thereto which are in his power." But,
unfortunately, the notion of happiness is so indefinite that although every man
wishes to attain it, yet he never can say definitely and consistently what it is
that he really wishes and wills. The reason of this is that all the elements
which belong to the notion of happiness are altogether empirical, i.e., they
must be borrowed from experience, and nevertheless the idea of happiness
requires an absolute whole, a maximum of welfare in my present and all future
circumstances. Now it is impossible that the most clear-sighted and at the same
time most powerful being (supposed finite) should frame to himself a definite
conception of what he really wills in this. Does he will riches, how much
anxiety, envy, and snares might he not thereby draw upon his shoulders? Does he
will knowledge and discernment, perhaps it might prove to be only an eye so much
the sharper to show him so much the more fearfully the evils that are now
concealed from him, and that cannot be avoided, or to impose more wants on his
desires, which already give him concern enough. Would he have long life? who
guarantees to him that it would not be a long misery? would he at least have
health? how often has uneasiness of the body restrained from excesses into which
perfect health would have allowed one to fall? and so on. In short, he is
unable, on any principle, to determine with certainty what would make him truly
happy; because to do so he would need to be omniscient. We cannot therefore act
on any definite principles to secure happiness, but only on empirical counsels,
e.g. of regimen, frugality, courtesy, reserve, etc., which experience teaches
do, on the average, most promote well-being. Hence it follows that the
imperatives of prudence do not, strictly speaking, command at all, that is, they
cannot present actions objectively as practically necessary; that they are
rather to be regarded as counsels (consilia) than precepts precepts of reason,
that the problem to determine certainly and universally what action would
promote the happiness of a rational being is completely insoluble, and
consequently no imperative respecting it is possible which should, in the strict
sense, command to do what makes happy; because happiness is not an ideal of
reason but of imagination, resting solely on empirical grounds, and it is vain
to expect that these should define an action by which one could attain the
totality of a series of consequences which is really endless. This imperative of
prudence would however be an analytical proposition if we assume that the means
to happiness could be certainly assigned; for it is distinguished from the
imperative of skill only by this, that in the latter the end is merely possible,
in the former it is given; as however both only ordain the means to that which
we suppose to be willed as an end, it follows that the imperative which ordains
the willing of the means to him who wills the end is in both cases analytical.
Thus there is no difficulty in regard to the possibility of an imperative of
this kind either.
On the other hand, the question how the imperative of morality
is possible, is undoubtedly one, the only one, demanding a solution, as this is
not at all hypothetical, and the objective necessity which it presents cannot
rest on any hypothesis, as is the case with the hypothetical imperatives. Only
here we must never leave out of consideration that we cannot make out by any
example, in other words empirically, whether there is such an imperative at all,
but it is rather to be feared that all those which seem to be categorical may
yet be at bottom hypothetical. For instance, when the precept is: "Thou shalt
not promise deceitfully"; and it is assumed that the necessity of this is not a
mere counsel to avoid some other evil, so that it should mean: "Thou shalt not
make a lying promise, lest if it become known thou shouldst destroy thy credit,"
but that an action of this kind must be regarded as evil in itself, so that the
imperative of the prohibition is categorical; then we cannot show with certainty
in any example that the will was determined merely by the law, without any other
spring of action, although it may appear to be so. For it is always possible
that fear of disgrace, perhaps also obscure dread of other dangers, may have a
secret influence on the will. Who can prove by experience the non-existence of a
cause when all that experience tells us is that we do not perceive it? But in
such a case the so-called moral imperative, which as such appears to be
categorical and unconditional, would in reality be only a pragmatic precept,
drawing our attention to our own interests and merely teaching us to take these
into consideration.
We shall therefore have to investigate a priori the possibility
of a categorical imperative, as we have not in this case the advantage of its
reality being given in experience, so that [the elucidation of] its possibility
should be requisite only for its explanation, not for its establishment. In the
meantime it may be discerned beforehand that the categorical imperative alone
has the purport of a practical law; all the rest may indeed be called principles
of the will but not laws, since whatever is only necessary for the attainment of
some arbitrary purpose may be considered as in itself contingent, and we can at
any time be free from the precept if we give up the purpose; on the contrary,
the unconditional command leaves the will no liberty to choose the opposite;
consequently it alone carries with it that necessity which we require in a law.
Secondly, in the case of this categorical imperative or law of
morality, the difficulty (of discerning its possibility) is a very profound one.
It is an a priori synthetical practical proposition; * and as there is so much
difficulty in discerning the possibility of speculative propositions of this
kind, it may readily be supposed that the difficulty will be no less with the
practical.
* I connect the act with the will
without presupposing any condition resulting from any inclination, but a priori,
and therefore necessarily (though only objectively, i.e., assuming the idea of a
reason possessing full power over all subjective motives). This is accordingly a
practical proposition which does not deduce the willing of an action by mere
analysis from another already presupposed (for we have not such a perfect will),
but connects it immediately with the conception of the will of a rational being,
as something not contained in it.
In this problem we will first inquire
whether the mere conception of a categorical imperative may not perhaps supply
us also with the formula of it, containing the proposition which alone can be a
categorical imperative; for even if we know the tenor of such an absolute
command, yet how it is possible will require further special and laborious
study, which we postpone to the last section.
When I conceive a hypothetical imperative, in general I do not
know beforehand what it will contain until I am given the condition. But when I
conceive a categorical imperative, I know at once what it contains. For as the
imperative contains besides the law only the necessity that the maxims * shall
conform to this law, while the law contains no conditions restricting it, there
remains nothing but the general statement that the maxim of the action should
conform to a universal law, and it is this conformity alone that the imperative
properly represents as necessary.
* A maxim is a subjective principle of
action, and must be distinguished from the objective principle, namely,
practical law. The former contains the practical rule set by reason according to
the conditions of the subject (often its ignorance or its inclinations), so that
it is the principle on which the subject acts; but the law is the objective
principle valid for every rational being, and is the principle on which it ought
to act that is an imperative.
There is therefore but one categorical
imperative, namely, this: Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same
time will that it should become a universal law.
Now if all imperatives of duty can be deduced from this one
imperative as from their principle, then, although it should remain undecided
what is called duty is not merely a vain notion, yet at least we shall be able
to show what we understand by it and what this notion means.
Since the universality of the law according to which effects are
produced constitutes what is properly called nature in the most general sense
(as to form), that is the existence of things so far as it is determined by
general laws, the imperative of duty may be expressed thus: Act as if the maxim
of thy action were to become by thy will a universal law of nature.
We will now enumerate a few duties, adopting the usual division
of them into duties to ourselves and ourselves and to others, and into perfect
and imperfect duties. *
* It must be noted here that I reserve
the division of duties for a future metaphysic of morals; so that I give it here
only as an arbitrary one (in order to arrange my examples). For the rest, I
understand by a perfect duty one that admits no exception in favour of
inclination and then I have not merely external but also internal perfect
duties. This is contrary to the use of the word adopted in the schools; but I do
not intend to justify there, as it is all one for my purpose whether it is
admitted or not.
1. A man reduced to despair by a series
of misfortunes feels wearied of life, but is still so far in possession of his
reason that he can ask himself whether it would not be contrary to his duty to
himself to take his own life. Now he inquires whether the maxim of his action
could become a universal law of nature. His maxim is: "From self-love I adopt it
as a principle to shorten my life when its longer duration is likely to bring
more evil than satisfaction." It is asked then simply whether this principle
founded on self-love can become a universal law of nature. Now we see at once
that a system of nature of which it should be a law to destroy life by means of
the very feeling whose special nature it is to impel to the improvement of life
would contradict itself and, therefore, could not exist as a system of nature;
hence that maxim cannot possibly exist as a universal law of nature and,
consequently, would be wholly inconsistent with the supreme principle of all
duty.
2. Another finds himself forced by necessity to borrow money. He
knows that he will not be able to repay it, but sees also that nothing will be
lent to him unless he promises stoutly to repay it in a definite time. He
desires to make this promise, but he has still so much conscience as to ask
himself: "Is it not unlawful and inconsistent with duty to get out of a
difficulty in this way?" Suppose however that he resolves to do so: then the
maxim of his action would be expressed thus: "When I think myself in want of
money, I will borrow money and promise to repay it, although I know that I never
can do so." Now this principle of self-love or of one's own advantage may
perhaps be consistent with my whole future welfare; but the question now is, "Is
it right?" I change then the suggestion of self-love into a universal law, and
state the question thus: "How would it be if my maxim were a universal law?"
Then I see at once that it could never hold as a universal law of nature, but
would necessarily contradict itself. For supposing it to be a universal law that
everyone when he thinks himself in a difficulty should be able to promise
whatever he pleases, with the purpose of not keeping his promise, the promise
itself would become impossible, as well as the end that one might have in view
in it, since no one would consider that anything was promised to him, but would
ridicule all such statements as vain pretences.
3. A third finds in himself a talent which with the help of some
culture might make him a useful man in many respects. But he finds himself in
comfortable circumstances and prefers to indulge in pleasure rather than to take
pains in enlarging and improving his happy natural capacities. He asks, however,
whether his maxim of neglect of his natural gifts, besides agreeing with his
inclination to indulgence, agrees also with what is called duty. He sees then
that a system of nature could indeed subsist with such a universal law although
men (like the South Sea islanders) should let their talents rest and resolve to
devote their lives merely to idleness, amusement, and propagation of their
species- in a word, to enjoyment; but he cannot possibly will that this should
be a universal law of nature, or be implanted in us as such by a natural
instinct. For, as a rational being, he necessarily wills that his faculties be
developed, since they serve him and have been given him, for all sorts of
possible purposes.
4. A fourth, who is in prosperity, while he sees that others
have to contend with great wretchedness and that he could help them, thinks:
"What concern is it of mine? Let everyone be as happy as Heaven pleases, or as
he can make himself; I will take nothing from him nor even envy him, only I do
not wish to contribute anything to his welfare or to his assistance in
distress!" Now no doubt if such a mode of thinking were a universal law, the
human race might very well subsist and doubtless even better than in a state in
which everyone talks of sympathy and good-will, or even takes care occasionally
to put it into practice, but, on the other side, also cheats when he can,
betrays the rights of men, or otherwise violates them. But although it is
possible that a universal law of nature might exist in accordance with that
maxim, it is impossible to will that such a principle should have the universal
validity of a law of nature. For a will which resolved this would contradict
itself, inasmuch as many cases might occur in which one would have need of the
love and sympathy of others, and in which, by such a law of nature, sprung from
his own will, he would deprive himself of all hope of the aid he desires.
These are a few of the many actual duties, or at least what we
regard as such, which obviously fall into two classes on the one principle that
we have laid down. We must be able to will that a maxim of our action should be
a universal law. This is the canon of the moral appreciation of the action
generally. Some actions are of such a character that their maxim cannot without
contradiction be even conceived as a universal law of nature, far from it being
possible that we should will that it should be so. In others this intrinsic
impossibility is not found, but still it is impossible to will that their maxim
should be raised to the universality of a law of nature, since such a will would
contradict itself It is easily seen that the former violate strict or rigorous
(inflexible) duty; the latter only laxer (meritorious) duty. Thus it has been
completely shown how all duties depend as regards the nature of the obligation
(not the object of the action) on the same principle.
If now we attend to ourselves on occasion of any transgression
of duty, we shall find that we in fact do not will that our maxim should be a
universal law, for that is impossible for us; on the contrary, we will that the
opposite should remain a universal law, only we assume the liberty of making an
exception in our own favour or (just for this time only) in favour of our
inclination. Consequently if we considered all cases from one and the same point
of view, namely, that of reason, we should find a contradiction in our own will,
namely, that a certain principle should be objectively necessary as a universal
law, and yet subjectively should not be universal, but admit of exceptions. As
however we at one moment regard our action from the point of view of a will
wholly conformed to reason, and then again look at the same action from the
point of view of a will affected by inclination, there is not really any
contradiction, but an antagonism of inclination to the precept of reason,
whereby the universality of the principle is changed into a mere generality, so
that the practical principle of reason shall meet the maxim half way. Now,
although this cannot be justified in our own impartial judgement, yet it proves
that we do really recognise the validity of the categorical imperative and (with
all respect for it) only allow ourselves a few exceptions, which we think
unimportant and forced from us.
We have thus established at least this much, that if duty is a
conception which is to have any import and real legislative authority for our
actions, it can only be expressed in categorical and not at all in hypothetical
imperatives. We have also, which is of great importance, exhibited clearly and
definitely for every practical application the content of the categorical
imperative, which must contain the principle of all duty if there is such a
thing at all. We have not yet, however, advanced so far as to prove a priori
that there actually is such an imperative, that there is a practical law which
commands absolutely of itself and without any other impulse, and that the
following of this law is duty.
With the view of attaining to this, it is of extreme importance
to remember that we must not allow ourselves to think of deducing the reality of
this principle from the particular attributes of human nature. For duty is to be
a practical, unconditional necessity of action; it must therefore hold for all
rational beings (to whom an imperative can apply at all), and for this reason
only be also a law for all human wills. On the contrary, whatever is deduced
from the particular natural characteristics of humanity, from certain feelings
and propensions, nay, even, if possible, from any particular tendency proper to
human reason, and which need not necessarily hold for the will of every rational
being; this may indeed supply us with a maxim, but not with a law; with a
subjective principle on which we may have a propension and inclination to act,
but not with an objective principle on which we should be enjoined to act, even
though all our propensions, inclinations, and natural dispositions were opposed
to it. In fact, the sublimity and intrinsic dignity of the command in duty are
so much the more evident, the less the subjective impulses favour it and the
more they oppose it, without being able in the slightest degree to weaken the
obligation of the law or to diminish its validity.
Here then we see philosophy brought to a critical position,
since it has to be firmly fixed, notwithstanding that it has nothing to support
it in heaven or earth. Here it must show its purity as absolute director of its
own laws, not the herald of those which are whispered to it by an implanted
sense or who knows what tutelary nature. Although these may be better than
nothing, yet they can never afford principles dictated by reason, which must
have their source wholly a priori and thence their commanding authority,
expecting everything from the supremacy of the law and the due respect for it,
nothing from inclination, or else condemning the man to self-contempt and inward
abhorrence.
Thus every empirical element is not only quite incapable of
being an aid to the principle of morality, but is even highly prejudicial to the
purity of morals, for the proper and inestimable worth of an absolutely good
will consists just in this, that the principle of action is free from all
influence of contingent grounds, which alone experience can furnish. We cannot
too much or too often repeat our warning against this lax and even mean habit of
thought which seeks for its principle amongst empirical motives and laws; for
human reason in its weariness is glad to rest on this pillow, and in a dream of
sweet illusions (in which, instead of Juno, it embraces a cloud) it substitutes
for morality a bastard patched up from limbs of various derivation, which looks
like anything one chooses to see in it, only not like virtue to one who has once
beheld her in her true form. *
* To behold virtue in her proper form is
nothing else but to contemplate morality stripped of all admixture of sensible
things and of every spurious ornament of reward or self-love. How much she then
eclipses everything else that appears charming to the affections, every one may
readily perceive with the least exertion of his reason, if it be not wholly
spoiled for abstraction.
The question then is this: "Is it a
necessary law for all rational beings that they should always judge of their
actions by maxims of which they can themselves will that they should serve as
universal laws?" If it is so, then it must be connected (altogether a priori)
with the very conception of the will of a rational being generally. But in order
to discover this connexion we must, however reluctantly, take a step into
metaphysic, although into a domain of it which is distinct from speculative
philosophy, namely, the metaphysic of morals. In a practical philosophy, where
it is not the reasons of what happens that we have to ascertain, but the laws of
what ought to happen, even although it never does, i.e., objective practical
laws, there it is not necessary to inquire into the reasons why anything pleases
or displeases, how the pleasure of mere sensation differs from taste, and
whether the latter is distinct from a general satisfaction of reason; on what
the feeling of pleasure or pain rests, and how from it desires and inclinations
arise, and from these again maxims by the co-operation of reason: for all this
belongs to an empirical psychology, which would constitute the second part of
physics, if we regard physics as the philosophy of nature, so far as it is based
on empirical laws. But here we are concerned with objective practical laws and,
consequently, with the relation of the will to itself so far as it is determined
by reason alone, in which case whatever has reference to anything empirical is
necessarily excluded; since if reason of itself alone determines the conduct
(and it is the possibility of this that we are now investigating), it must
necessarily do so a priori.
The will is conceived as a faculty of determining oneself to
action in accordance with the conception of certain laws. And such a faculty can
be found only in rational beings. Now that which serves the will as the
objective ground of its self-determination is the end, and, if this is assigned
by reason alone, it must hold for all rational beings. On the other hand, that
which merely contains the ground of possibility of the action of which the
effect is the end, this is called the means. The subjective ground of the desire
is the spring, the objective ground of the volition is the motive; hence the
distinction between subjective ends which rest on springs, and objective ends
which depend on motives valid for every rational being. Practical principles are
formal when they abstract from all subjective ends; they are material when they
assume these, and therefore particular springs of action. The ends which a
rational being proposes to himself at pleasure as effects of his actions
(material ends) are all only relative, for it is only their relation to the
particular desires of the subject that gives them their worth, which therefore
cannot furnish principles universal and necessary for all rational beings and
for every volition, that is to say practical laws. Hence all these relative ends
can give rise only to hypothetical imperatives.
Supposing, however, that there were something whose existence
has in itself an absolute worth, something which, being an end in itself, could
be a source of definite laws; then in this and this alone would lie the source
of a possible categorical imperative, i.e., a practical law.
Now I say: man and generally any rational being exists as an end
in himself, not merely as a means to be arbitrarily used by this or that will,
but in all his actions, whether they concern himself or other rational beings,
must be always regarded at the same time as an end. All objects of the
inclinations have only a conditional worth, for if the inclinations and the
wants founded on them did not exist, then their object would be without value.
But the inclinations, themselves being sources of want, are so far from having
an absolute worth for which they should be desired that on the contrary it must
be the universal wish of every rational being to be wholly free from them. Thus
the worth of any object which is to be acquired by our action is always
conditional. Beings whose existence depends not on our will but on nature's,
have nevertheless, if they are irrational beings, only a relative value as
means, and are therefore called things; rational beings, on the contrary, are
called persons, because their very nature points them out as ends in themselves,
that is as something which must not be used merely as means, and so far
therefore restricts freedom of action (and is an object of respect). These,
therefore, are not merely subjective ends whose existence has a worth for us as
an effect of our action, but objective ends, that is, things whose existence is
an end in itself; an end moreover for which no other can be substituted, which
they should subserve merely as means, for otherwise nothing whatever would
possess absolute worth; but if all worth were conditioned and therefore
contingent, then there would be no supreme practical principle of reason
whatever.
If then there is a supreme practical principle or, in respect of
the human will, a categorical imperative, it must be one which, being drawn from
the conception of that which is necessarily an end for everyone because it is an
end in itself, constitutes an objective principle of will, and can therefore
serve as a universal practical law. The foundation of this principle is:
rational nature exists as an end in itself. Man necessarily conceives his own
existence as being so; so far then this is a subjective principle of human
actions. But every other rational being regards its existence similarly, just on
the same rational principle that holds for me: * so that it is at the same time
an objective principle, from which as a supreme practical law all laws of the
will must be capable of being deduced. Accordingly the practical imperative will
be as follows: So act as to treat humanity, whether in thine own person or in
that of any other, in every case as an end withal, never as means only. We will
now inquire whether this can be practically carried out.
* This proposition is here stated as a
postulate. The ground of it will be found in the concluding section.
To abide by the previous examples:
Firstly, under the head of necessary duty to oneself: He who
contemplates suicide should ask himself whether his action can be consistent
with the idea of humanity as an end in itself. If he destroys himself in order
to escape from painful circumstances, he uses a person merely as a mean to
maintain a tolerable condition up to the end of life. But a man is not a thing,
that is to say, something which can be used merely as means, but must in all his
actions be always considered as an end in himself. I cannot, therefore, dispose
in any way of a man in my own person so as to mutilate him, to damage or kill
him. (It belongs to ethics proper to define this principle more precisely, so as
to avoid all misunderstanding, e. g., as to the amputation of the limbs in order
to preserve myself, as to exposing my life to danger with a view to preserve it,
etc. This question is therefore omitted here.)
Secondly, as regards necessary duties, or those of strict
obligation, towards others: He who is thinking of making a lying promise to
others will see at once that he would be using another man merely as a mean,
without the latter containing at the same time the end in himself. For he whom I
propose by such a promise to use for my own purposes cannot possibly assent to
my mode of acting towards him and, therefore, cannot himself contain the end of
this action. This violation of the principle of humanity in other men is more
obvious if we take in examples of attacks on the freedom and property of others.
For then it is clear that he who transgresses the rights of men intends to use
the person of others merely as a means, without considering that as rational
beings they ought always to be esteemed also as ends, that is, as beings who
must be capable of containing in themselves the end of the very same action. *
* Let it not be thought that the common
"quod tibi non vis fieri, etc." could serve here as the rule or principle. For
it is only a deduction from the former, though with several limitations; it
cannot be a universal law, for it does not contain the principle of duties to
oneself, nor of the duties of benevolence to others (for many a one would gladly
consent that others should not benefit him, provided only that he might be
excused from showing benevolence to them), nor finally that of duties of strict
obligation to one another, for on this principle the criminal might argue
against the judge who punishes him, and so on.
Thirdly, as regards contingent
(meritorious) duties to oneself: It is not enough that the action does not
violate humanity in our own person as an end in itself, it must also harmonize
with it. Now there are in humanity capacities of greater perfection, which
belong to the end that nature has in view in regard to humanity in ourselves as
the subject: to neglect these might perhaps be consistent with the maintenance
of humanity as an end in itself, but not with the advancement of this end.
Fourthly, as regards meritorious duties towards others: The
natural end which all men have is their own happiness. Now humanity might indeed
subsist, although no one should contribute anything to the happiness of others,
provided he did not intentionally withdraw anything from it; but after all this
would only harmonize negatively not positively with humanity as an end in
itself, if every one does not also endeavour, as far as in him lies, to forward
the ends of others. For the ends of any subject which is an end in himself ought
as far as possible to be my ends also, if that conception is to have its full
effect with me.
This principle, that humanity and generally every rational
nature is an end in itself (which is the supreme limiting condition of every
man's freedom of action), is not borrowed from experience, firstly, because it
is universal, applying as it does to all rational beings whatever, and
experience is not capable of determining anything about them; secondly, because
it does not present humanity as an end to men (subjectively), that is as an
object which men do of themselves actually adopt as an end; but as an objective
end, which must as a law constitute the supreme limiting condition of all our
subjective ends, let them be what we will; it must therefore spring from pure
reason. In fact the objective principle of all practical legislation lies
(according to the first principle) in the rule and its form of universality
which makes it capable of being a law (say, e. g., a law of nature); but the
subjective principle is in the end; now by the second principle the subject of
all ends is each rational being, inasmuch as it is an end in itself. Hence
follows the third practical principle of the will, which is the ultimate
condition of its harmony with universal practical reason, viz.: the idea of the
will of every rational being as a universally legislative will.
On this principle all maxims are rejected which are inconsistent
with the will being itself universal legislator. Thus the will is not subject
simply to the law, but so subject that it must be regarded as itself giving the
law and, on this ground only, subject to the law (of which it can regard itself
as the author).
In the previous imperatives, namely, that based on the
conception of the conformity of actions to general laws, as in a physical system
of nature, and that based on the universal prerogative of rational beings as
ends in themselves- these imperatives, just because they were conceived as
categorical, excluded from any share in their authority all admixture of any
interest as a spring of action; they were, however, only assumed to be
categorical, because such an assumption was necessary to explain the conception
of duty. But we could not prove independently that there are practical
propositions which command categorically, nor can it be proved in this section;
one thing, however, could be done, namely, to indicate in the imperative itself,
by some determinate expression, that in the case of volition from duty all
interest is renounced, which is the specific criterion of categorical as
distinguished from hypothetical imperatives. This is done in the present (third)
formula of the principle, namely, in the idea of the will of every rational
being as a universally legislating will.
For although a will which is subject to laws may be attached to
this law by means of an interest, yet a will which is itself a supreme lawgiver
so far as it is such cannot possibly depend on any interest, since a will so
dependent would itself still need another law restricting the interest of its
self-love by the condition that it should be valid as universal law.
Thus the principle that every human will is a will which in all
its maxims gives universal laws, * provided it be otherwise justified, would be
very well adapted to be the categorical imperative, in this respect, namely,
that just because of the idea of universal legislation it is not based on
interest, and therefore it alone among all possible imperatives can be
unconditional. Or still better, converting the proposition, if there is a
categorical imperative (i.e., a law for the will of every rational being), it
can only command that everything be done from maxims of one's will regarded as a
will which could at the same time will that it should itself give universal
laws, for in that case only the practical principle and the imperative which it
obeys are unconditional, since they cannot be based on any interest.
* I may be excused from adducing
examples to elucidate this principle, as those which have already been used to
elucidate the categorical imperative and its formula would all serve for the
like purpose here.
Looking back now on all previous
attempts to discover the principle of morality, we need not wonder why they all
failed. It was seen that man was bound to laws by duty, but it was not observed
that the laws to which he is subject are only those of his own giving, though at
the same time they are universal, and that he is only bound to act in conformity
with his own will; a will, however, which is designed by nature to give
universal laws. For when one has conceived man only as subject to a law (no
matter what), then this law required some interest, either by way of attraction
or constraint, since it did not originate as a law from his own will, but this
will was according to a law obliged by something else to act in a certain
manner. Now by this necessary consequence all the labour spent in finding a
supreme principle of duty was irrevocably lost. For men never elicited duty, but
only a necessity of acting from a certain interest. Whether this interest was
private or otherwise, in any case the imperative must be conditional and could
not by any means be capable of being a moral command. I will therefore call this
the principle of autonomy of the will, in contrast with every other which I
accordingly reckon as heteronomy.
The conception of the will of every rational being as one which
must consider itself as giving in all the maxims of its will universal laws, so
as to judge itself and its actions from this point of view- this conception
leads to another which depends on it and is very fruitful, namely that of a
kingdom of ends.
By a kingdom I understand the union of different rational beings
in a system by common laws. Now since it is by laws that ends are determined as
regards their universal validity, hence, if we abstract from the personal
differences of rational beings and likewise from all the content of their
private ends, we shall be able to conceive all ends combined in a systematic
whole (including both rational beings as ends in themselves, and also the
special ends which each may propose to himself), that is to say, we can conceive
a kingdom of ends, which on the preceding principles is possible.
For all rational beings come under the law that each of them
must treat itself and all others never merely as means, but in every case at the
same time as ends in themselves. Hence results a systematic union of rational
being by common objective laws, i.e., a kingdom which may be called a kingdom of
ends, since what these laws have in view is just the relation of these beings to
one another as ends and means. It is certainly only an ideal.
A rational being belongs as a member to the kingdom of ends
when, although giving universal laws in it, he is also himself subject to these
laws. He belongs to it as sovereign when, while giving laws, he is not subject
to the will of any other.
A rational being must always regard himself as giving laws
either as member or as sovereign in a kingdom of ends which is rendered possible
by the freedom of will. He cannot, however, maintain the latter position merely
by the maxims of his will, but only in case he is a completely independent being
without wants and with unrestricted power adequate to his will.
Morality consists then in the reference of all action to the
legislation which alone can render a kingdom of ends possible. This legislation
must be capable of existing in every rational being and of emanating from his
will, so that the principle of this will is never to act on any maxim which
could not without contradiction be also a universal law and, accordingly, always
so to act that the will could at the same time regard itself as giving in its
maxims universal laws. If now the maxims of rational beings are not by their own
nature coincident with this objective principle, then the necessity of acting on
it is called practical necessitation, i.e., duty. Duty does not apply to the
sovereign in the kingdom of ends, but it does to every member of it and to all
in the same degree.
The practical necessity of acting on this principle, i.e., duty,
does not rest at all on feelings, impulses, or inclinations, but solely on the
relation of rational beings to one another, a relation in which the will of a
rational being must always be regarded as legislative, since otherwise it could
not be conceived as an end in itself. Reason then refers every maxim of the
will, regarding it as legislating universally, to every other will and also to
every action towards oneself; and this not on account of any other practical
motive or any future advantage, but from the idea of the dignity of a rational
being, obeying no law but that which he himself also gives.
In the kingdom of ends everything has either value or dignity.
Whatever has a value can be replaced by something else which is equivalent;
whatever, on the other hand, is above all value, and therefore admits of no
equivalent, has a dignity.
Whatever has reference to the general inclinations and wants of
mankind has a market value; whatever, without presupposing a want, corresponds
to a certain taste, that is to a satisfaction in the mere purposeless play of
our faculties, has a fancy value; but that which constitutes the condition under
which alone anything can be an end in itself, this has not merely a relative
worth, i.e., value, but an intrinsic worth, that is, dignity.
Now morality is the condition under which alone a rational being
can be an end in himself, since by this alone is it possible that he should be a
legislating member in the kingdom of ends. Thus morality, and humanity as
capable of it, is that which alone has dignity. Skill and diligence in labour
have a market value; wit, lively imagination, and humour, have fancy value; on
the other hand, fidelity to promises, benevolence from principle (not from
instinct), have an intrinsic worth. Neither nature nor art contains anything
which in default of these it could put in their place, for their worth consists
not in the effects which spring from them, not in the use and advantage which
they secure, but in the disposition of mind, that is, the maxims of the will
which are ready to manifest themselves in such actions, even though they should
not have the desired effect. These actions also need no recommendation from any
subjective taste or sentiment, that they may be looked on with immediate favour
and satisfaction: they need no immediate propension or feeling for them; they
exhibit the will that performs them as an object of an immediate respect, and
nothing but reason is required to impose them on the will; not to flatter it
into them, which, in the case of duties, would be a contradiction. This
estimation therefore shows that the worth of such a disposition is dignity, and
places it infinitely above all value, with which it cannot for a moment be
brought into comparison or competition without as it were violating its
sanctity.
What then is it which justifies virtue or the morally good
disposition, in making such lofty claims? It is nothing less than the privilege
it secures to the rational being of participating in the giving of universal
laws, by which it qualifies him to be a member of a possible kingdom of ends, a
privilege to which he was already destined by his own nature as being an end in
himself and, on that account, legislating in the kingdom of ends; free as
regards all laws of physical nature, and obeying those only which he himself
gives, and by which his maxims can belong to a system of universal law, to which
at the same time he submits himself. For nothing has any worth except what the
law assigns it. Now the legislation itself which assigns the worth of everything
must for that very reason possess dignity, that is an unconditional incomparable
worth; and the word respect alone supplies a becoming expression for the esteem
which a rational being must have for it. Autonomy then is the basis of the
dignity of human and of every rational nature.
The three modes of presenting the principle of morality that
have been adduced are at bottom only so many formulae of the very same law, and
each of itself involves the other two. There is, however, a difference in them,
but it is rather subjectively than objectively practical, intended namely to
bring an idea of the reason nearer to intuition (by means of a certain analogy)
and thereby nearer to feeling. All maxims, in fact, have:
1. A form, consisting in universality; and in this view the
formula of the moral imperative is expressed thus, that the maxims must be so
chosen as if they were to serve as universal laws of nature.
2. A matter, namely, an end, and here the formula says that the
rational being, as it is an end by its own nature and therefore an end in
itself, must in every maxim serve as the condition limiting all merely relative
and arbitrary ends.
3. A complete characterization of all maxims by means of that
formula, namely, that all maxims ought by their own legislation to harmonize
with a possible kingdom of ends as with a kingdom of nature. * There is a
progress here in the order of the categories of unity of the form of the will
(its universality), plurality of the matter (the objects, i.e., the ends), and
totality of the system of these. In forming our moral judgement of actions, it
is better to proceed always on the strict method and start from the general
formula of the categorical imperative: Act according to a maxim which can at the
same time make itself a universal law. If, however, we wish to gain an entrance
for the moral law, it is very useful to bring one and the same action under the
three specified conceptions, and thereby as far as possible to bring it nearer
to intuition.
* Teleology considers nature as a
kingdom of ends; ethics regards a possible kingdom of ends as a kingdom nature.
In the first case, the kingdom of ends is a theoretical idea, adopted to explain
what actually is. In the latter it is a practical idea, adopted to bring about
that which is not yet, but which can be realized by our conduct, namely, if it
conforms to this idea.
We can now end where we started at the
beginning, namely, with the conception of a will unconditionally good. That will
is absolutely good which cannot be evil- in other words, whose maxim, if made a
universal law, could never contradict itself. This principle, then, is its
supreme law: "Act always on such a maxim as thou canst at the same time will to
be a universal law"; this is the sole condition under which a will can never
contradict itself; and such an imperative is categorical. Since the validity of
the will as a universal law for possible actions is analogous to the universal
connexion of the existence of things by general laws, which is the formal notion
of nature in general, the categorical imperative can also be expressed thus: Act
on maxims which can at the same time have for their object themselves as
universal laws of nature. Such then is the formula of an absolutely good will.
Rational nature is distinguished from the rest of nature by
this, that it sets before itself an end. This end would be the matter of every
good will. But since in the idea of a will that is absolutely good without being
limited by any condition (of attaining this or that end) we must abstract wholly
from every end to be effected (since this would make every will only relatively
good), it follows that in this case the end must be conceived, not as an end to
be effected, but as an independently existing end. Consequently it is conceived
only negatively, i.e., as that which we must never act against and which,
therefore, must never be regarded merely as means, but must in every volition be
esteemed as an end likewise. Now this end can be nothing but the subject of all
possible ends, since this is also the subject of a possible absolutely good
will; for such a will cannot without contradiction be postponed to any other
object. The principle: "So act in regard to every rational being (thyself and
others), that he may always have place in thy maxim as an end in himself," is
accordingly essentially identical with this other: "Act upon a maxim which, at
the same time, involves its own universal validity for every rational being."
For that in using means for every end I should limit my maxim by the condition
of its holding good as a law for every subject, this comes to the same thing as
that the fundamental principle of all maxims of action must be that the subject
of all ends, i.e., the rational being himself, be never employed merely as
means, but as the supreme condition restricting the use of all means, that is in
every case as an end likewise.
It follows incontestably that, to whatever laws any rational
being may be subject, he being an end in himself must be able to regard himself
as also legislating universally in respect of these same laws, since it is just
this fitness of his maxims for universal legislation that distinguishes him as
an end in himself; also it follows that this implies his dignity (prerogative)
above all mere physical beings, that he must always take his maxims from the
point of view which regards himself and, likewise, every other rational being as
law-giving beings (on which account they are called persons). In this way a
world of rational beings (mundus intelligibilis) is possible as a kingdom of
ends, and this by virtue of the legislation proper to all persons as members.
Therefore every rational being must so act as if he were by his maxims in every
case a legislating member in the universal kingdom of ends. The formal principle
of these maxims is: "So act as if thy maxim were to serve likewise as the
universal law (of all rational beings)." A kingdom of ends is thus only possible
on the analogy of a kingdom of nature, the former however only by maxims, that
is self-imposed rules, the latter only by the laws of efficient causes acting
under necessitation from without. Nevertheless, although the system of nature is
looked upon as a machine, yet so far as it has reference to rational beings as
its ends, it is given on this account the name of a kingdom of nature. Now such
a kingdom of ends would be actually realized by means of maxims conforming to
the canon which the categorical imperative prescribes to all rational beings, if
they were universally followed. But although a rational being, even if he
punctually follows this maxim himself, cannot reckon upon all others being
therefore true to the same, nor expect that the kingdom of nature and its
orderly arrangements shall be in harmony with him as a fitting member, so as to
form a kingdom of ends to which he himself contributes, that is to say, that it
shall favour his expectation of happiness, still that law: "Act according to the
maxims of a member of a merely possible kingdom of ends legislating in it
universally," remains in its full force, inasmuch as it commands categorically.
And it is just in this that the paradox lies; that the mere dignity of man as a
rational creature, without any other end or advantage to be attained thereby, in
other words, respect for a mere idea, should yet serve as an inflexible precept
of the will, and that it is precisely in this independence of the maxim on all
such springs of action that its sublimity consists; and it is this that makes
every rational subject worthy to be a legislative member in the kingdom of ends:
for otherwise he would have to be conceived only as subject to the physical law
of his wants. And although we should suppose the kingdom of nature and the
kingdom of ends to be united under one sovereign, so that the latter kingdom
thereby ceased to be a mere idea and acquired true reality, then it would no
doubt gain the accession of a strong spring, but by no means any increase of its
intrinsic worth. For this sole absolute lawgiver must, notwithstanding this, be
always conceived as estimating the worth of rational beings only by their
disinterested behaviour, as prescribed to themselves from that idea [the dignity
of man] alone. The essence of things is not altered by their external relations,
and that which, abstracting from these, alone constitutes the absolute worth of
man, is also that by which he must be judged, whoever the judge may be, and even
by the Supreme Being. Morality, then, is the relation of actions to the relation
of actions will, that is, to the autonomy of potential universal legislation by
its maxims. An action that is consistent with the autonomy of the will is
permitted; one that does not agree therewith is forbidden. A will whose maxims
necessarily coincide with the laws of autonomy is a holy will, good absolutely.
The dependence of a will not absolutely good on the principle of autonomy (moral
necessitation) is obligation. This, then, cannot be applied to a holy being. The
objective necessity of actions from obligation is called duty.
From what has just been said, it is easy to see how it happens
that, although the conception of duty implies subjection to the law, we yet
ascribe a certain dignity and sublimity to the person who fulfils all his
duties. There is not, indeed, any sublimity in him, so far as he is subject to
the moral law; but inasmuch as in regard to that very law he is likewise a
legislator, and on that account alone subject to it, he has sublimity. We have
also shown above that neither fear nor inclination, but simply respect for the
law, is the spring which can give actions a moral worth. Our own will, so far as
we suppose it to act only under the condition that its maxims are potentially
universal laws, this ideal will which is possible to us is the proper object of
respect; and the dignity of humanity consists just in this capacity of being
universally legislative, though with the condition that it is itself subject to
this same legislation.
The Autonomy of the Will as the Supreme
Principle of Morality
Autonomy of the will is that property of
it by which it is a law to itself (independently of any property of the objects
of volition). The principle of autonomy then is: "Always so to choose that the
same volition shall comprehend the maxims of our choice as a universal law." We
cannot prove that this practical rule is an imperative, i.e., that the will of
every rational being is necessarily bound to it as a condition, by a mere
analysis of the conceptions which occur in it, since it is a synthetical
proposition; we must advance beyond the cognition of the objects to a critical
examination of the subject, that is, of the pure practical reason, for this
synthetic proposition which commands apodeictically must be capable of being
cognized wholly a priori. This matter, however, does not belong to the present
section. But that the principle of autonomy in question is the sole principle of
morals can be readily shown by mere analysis of the conceptions of morality. For
by this analysis we find that its principle must be a categorical imperative and
that what this commands is neither more nor less than this very autonomy.
Heteronomy of the Will as the Source of
all spurious Principles
of Morality
If the will seeks the law which is to
determine it anywhere else than in the fitness of its maxims to be universal
laws of its own dictation, consequently if it goes out of itself and seeks this
law in the character of any of its objects, there always results heteronomy. The
will in that case does not give itself the law, but it is given by the object
through its relation to the will. This relation, whether it rests on inclination
or on conceptions of reason, only admits of hypothetical imperatives: "I ought
to do something because I wish for something else." On the contrary, the moral,
and therefore categorical, imperative says: "I ought to do so and so, even
though I should not wish for anything else." E.g., the former says: "I ought not
to lie, if I would retain my reputation"; the latter says: "I ought not to lie,
although it should not bring me the least discredit." The latter therefore must
so far abstract from all objects that they shall have no influence on the will,
in order that practical reason (will) may not be restricted to administering an
interest not belonging to it, but may simply show its own commanding authority
as the supreme legislation. Thus, e.g., I ought to endeavour to promote the
happiness of others, not as if its realization involved any concern of mine
(whether by immediate inclination or by any satisfaction indirectly gained
through reason), but simply because a maxim which excludes it cannot be
comprehended as a universal law in one and the same volition.
Classification of all Principles of
Morality which can be
founded on the Conception of Heteronomy
Here as elsewhere human reason in its
pure use, so long as it was not critically examined, has first tried all
possible wrong ways before it succeeded in finding the one true way.
All principles which can be taken from this point of view are
either empirical or rational. The former, drawn from the principle of happiness,
are built on physical or moral feelings; the latter, drawn from the principle of
perfection, are built either on the rational conception of perfection as a
possible effect, or on that of an independent perfection (the will of God) as
the determining cause of our will.
Empirical principles are wholly incapable of serving as a
foundation for moral laws. For the universality with which these should hold for
all rational beings without distinction, the unconditional practical necessity
which is thereby imposed on them, is lost when their foundation is taken from
the particular constitution of human nature, or the accidental circumstances in
which it is placed. The principle of private happiness, however, is the most
objectionable, not merely because it is false, and experience contradicts the
supposition that prosperity is always proportioned to good conduct, nor yet
merely because it contributes nothing to the establishment of morality- since it
is quite a different thing to make a prosperous man and a good man, or to make
one prudent and sharp-sighted for his own interests and to make him virtuous-
but because the springs it provides for morality are such as rather undermine it
and destroy its sublimity, since they put the motives to virtue and to vice in
the same class and only teach us to make a better calculation, the specific
difference between virtue and vice being entirely extinguished. On the other
hand, as to moral feeling, this supposed special sense, * the appeal to it is
indeed superficial when those who cannot think believe that feeling will help
them out, even in what concerns general laws: and besides, feelings, which
naturally differ infinitely in degree, cannot furnish a uniform standard of good
and evil, nor has anyone a right to form judgements for others by his own
feelings: nevertheless this moral feeling is nearer to morality and its dignity
in this respect, that it pays virtue the honour of ascribing to her immediately
the satisfaction and esteem we have for her and does not, as it were, tell her
to her face that we are not attached to her by her beauty but by profit.
* I class the principle of moral feeling
under that of happiness, because every empirical interest promises to contribute
to our well-being by the agreeableness that a thing affords, whether it be
immediately and without a view to profit, or whether profit be regarded. We must
likewise, with Hutcheson, class the principle of sympathy with the happiness of
others under his assumed moral sense.
Amongst the rational principles of
morality, the ontological conception of perfection, notwithstanding its defects,
is better than the theological conception which derives morality from a Divine
absolutely perfect will. The former is, no doubt, empty and indefinite and
consequently useless for finding in the boundless field of possible reality the
greatest amount suitable for us; moreover, in attempting to distinguish
specifically the reality of which we are now speaking from every other, it
inevitably tends to turn in a circle and cannot avoid tacitly presupposing the
morality which it is to explain; it is nevertheless preferable to the
theological view, first, because we have no intuition of the divine perfection
and can only deduce it from our own conceptions, the most important of which is
that of morality, and our explanation would thus be involved in a gross circle;
and, in the next place, if we avoid this, the only notion of the Divine will
remaining to us is a conception made up of the attributes of desire of glory and
dominion, combined with the awful conceptions of might and vengeance, and any
system of morals erected on this foundation would be directly opposed to
morality.
However, if I had to choose between the notion of the moral
sense and that of perfection in general (two systems which at least do not
weaken morality, although they are totally incapable of serving as its
foundation), then I should decide for the latter, because it at least withdraws
the decision of the question from the sensibility and brings it to the court of
pure reason; and although even here it decides nothing, it at all events
preserves the indefinite idea (of a will good in itself free from corruption,
until it shall be more precisely defined.
For the rest I think I may be excused here from a detailed
refutation of all these doctrines; that would only be superfluous labour, since
it is so easy, and is probably so well seen even by those whose office requires
them to decide for one of these theories (because their hearers would not
tolerate suspension of judgement). But what interests us more here is to know
that the prime foundation of morality laid down by all these principles is
nothing but heteronomy of the will, and for this reason they must necessarily
miss their aim.
In every case where an object of the will has to be supposed, in
order that the rule may be prescribed which is to determine the will, there the
rule is simply heteronomy; the imperative is conditional, namely, if or because
one wishes for this object, one should act so and so: hence it can never command
morally, that is, categorically. Whether the object determines the will by means
of inclination, as in the principle of private happiness, or by means of reason
directed to objects of our possible volition generally, as in the principle of
perfection, in either case the will never determines itself immediately by the
conception of the action, but only by the influence which the foreseen effect of
the action has on the will; I ought to do something, on this account, because I
wish for something else; and here there must be yet another law assumed in me as
its subject, by which I necessarily will this other thing, and this law again
requires an imperative to restrict this maxim. For the influence which the
conception of an object within the reach of our faculties can exercise on the
will of the subject, in consequence of its natural properties, depends on the
nature of the subject, either the sensibility (inclination and taste), or the
understanding and reason, the employment of which is by the peculiar
constitution of their nature attended with satisfaction. It follows that the law
would be, properly speaking, given by nature, and, as such, it must be known and
proved by experience and would consequently be contingent and therefore
incapable of being an apodeictic practical rule, such as the moral rule must be.
Not only so, but it is inevitably only heteronomy; the will does not give itself
the law, but is given by a foreign impulse by means of a particular natural
constitution of the subject adapted to receive it. An absolutely good will,
then, the principle of which must be a categorical imperative, will be
indeterminate as regards all objects and will contain merely the form of
volition generally, and that as autonomy, that is to say, the capability of the
maxims of every good will to make themselves a universal law, is itself the only
law which the will of every rational being imposes on itself, without needing to
assume any spring or interest as a foundation.
How such a synthetical practical a priori proposition is
possible, and why it is necessary, is a problem whose solution does not lie
within the bounds of the metaphysic of morals; and we have not here affirmed its
truth, much less professed to have a proof of it in our power. We simply showed
by the development of the universally received notion of morality that an
autonomy of the will is inevitably connected with it, or rather is its
foundation. Whoever then holds morality to be anything real, and not a
chimerical idea without any truth, must likewise admit the principle of it that
is here assigned. This section then, like the first, was merely analytical. Now
to prove that morality is no creation of the brain, which it cannot be if the
categorical imperative and with it the autonomy of the will is true, and as an a
priori principle absolutely necessary, this supposes the possibility of a
synthetic use of pure practical reason, which however we cannot venture on
without first giving a critical examination of this faculty of reason. In the
concluding section we shall give the principal outlines of this critical
examination as far as is sufficient for our purpose.
SEC_3
THIRD SECTION
TRANSITION FROM THE METAPHYSIC OF
MORALS TO THE
CRITIQUE OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON
The Concept of Freedom is the Key that
explains the Autonomy of the Will
The will is a kind of causality
belonging to living beings in so far as they are rational, and freedom would be
this property of such causality that it can be efficient, independently of
foreign causes determining it; just as physical necessity is the property that
the causality of all irrational beings has of being determined to activity by
the influence of foreign causes.
The preceding definition of freedom is negative and therefore
unfruitful for the discovery of its essence, but it leads to a positive
conception which is so much the more full and fruitful.
Since the conception of causality involves that of laws,
according to which, by something that we call cause, something else, namely the
effect, must be produced; hence, although freedom is not a property of the will
depending on physical laws, yet it is not for that reason lawless; on the
contrary it must be a causality acting according to immutable laws, but of a
peculiar kind; otherwise a free will would be an absurdity. Physical necessity
is a heteronomy of the efficient causes, for every effect is possible only
according to this law, that something else determines the efficient cause to
exert its causality. What else then can freedom of the will be but autonomy,
that is, the property of the will to be a law to itself? But the proposition:
"The will is in every action a law to itself," only expresses the principle: "To
act on no other maxim than that which can also have as an object itself as a
universal law." Now this is precisely the formula of the categorical imperative
and is the principle of morality, so that a free will and a will subject to
moral laws are one and the same.
On the hypothesis, then, of freedom of the will, morality
together with its principle follows from it by mere analysis of the conception.
However, the latter is a synthetic proposition; viz., an absolutely good will is
that whose maxim can always include itself regarded as a universal law; for this
property of its maxim can never be discovered by analysing the conception of an
absolutely good will. Now such synthetic propositions are only possible in this
way: that the two cognitions are connected together by their union with a third
in which they are both to be found. The positive concept of freedom furnishes
this third cognition, which cannot, as with physical causes, be the nature of
the sensible world (in the concept of which we find conjoined the concept of
something in relation as cause to something else as effect). We cannot now at
once show what this third is to which freedom points us and of which we have an
idea a priori, nor can we make intelligible how the concept of freedom is shown
to be legitimate from principles of pure practical reason and with it the
possibility of a categorical imperative; but some further preparation is
required.
Freedom must be presupposed as a
Property of the Will
of all Rational Beings
It is not enough to predicate freedom of
our own will, from Whatever reason, if we have not sufficient grounds for
predicating the same of all rational beings. For as morality serves as a law for
us only because we are rational beings, it must also hold for all rational
beings; and as it must be deduced simply from the property of freedom, it must
be shown that freedom also is a property of all rational beings. It is not
enough, then, to prove it from certain supposed experiences of human nature
(which indeed is quite impossible, and it can only be shown a priori), but we
must show that it belongs to the activity of all rational beings endowed with a
will. Now I say every being that cannot act except under the idea of freedom is
just for that reason in a practical point of view really free, that is to say,
all laws which are inseparably connected with freedom have the same force for
him as if his will had been shown to be free in itself by a proof theoretically
conclusive. * Now I affirm that we must attribute to every rational being which
has a will that it has also the idea of freedom and acts entirely under this
idea. For in such a being we conceive a reason that is practical, that is, has
causality in reference to its objects. Now we cannot possibly conceive a reason
consciously receiving a bias from any other quarter with respect to its
judgements, for then the subject would ascribe the determination of its
judgement not to its own reason, but to an impulse. It must regard itself as the
author of its principles independent of foreign influences. Consequently as
practical reason or as the will of a rational being it must regard itself as
free, that is to say, the will of such a being cannot be a will of its own
except under the idea of freedom. This idea must therefore in a practical point
of view be ascribed to every rational being.
* I adopt this method of assuming
freedom merely as an idea which rational beings suppose in their actions, in
order to avoid the necessity of proving it in its theoretical aspect also. The
former is sufficient for my purpose; for even though the speculative proof
should not be made out, yet a being that cannot act except with the idea of
freedom is bound by the same laws that would oblige a being who was actually
free. Thus we can escape here from the onus which presses on the theory.
Of the Interest attaching to the Ideas
of Morality
We have finally reduced the definite
conception of morality to the idea of freedom. This latter, however, we could
not prove to be actually a property of ourselves or of human nature; only we saw
that it must be presupposed if we would conceive a being as rational and
conscious of its causality in respect of its actions, i.e., as endowed with a
will; and so we find that on just the same grounds we must ascribe to every
being endowed with reason and will this attribute of determining itself to
action under the idea of its freedom.
Now it resulted also from the presupposition of these ideas that
we became aware of a law that the subjective principles of action, i.e., maxims,
must always be so assumed that they can also hold as objective, that is,
universal principles, and so serve as universal laws of our own dictation. But
why then should I subject myself to this principle and that simply as a rational
being, thus also subjecting to it all other being endowed with reason? I will
allow that no interest urges me to this, for that would not give a categorical
imperative, but I must take an interest in it and discern how this comes to
pass; for this properly an "I ought" is properly an "I would," valid for every
rational being, provided only that reason determined his actions without any
hindrance. But for beings that are in addition affected as we are by springs of
a different kind, namely, sensibility, and in whose case that is not always done
which reason alone would do, for these that necessity is expressed only as an
"ought," and the subjective necessity is different from the objective.
It seems then as if the moral law, that is, the principle of
autonomy of the will, were properly speaking only presupposed in the idea of
freedom, and as if we could not prove its reality and objective necessity
independently. In that case we should still have gained something considerable
by at least determining the true principle more exactly than had previously been
done; but as regards its validity and the practical necessity of subjecting
oneself to it, we should not have advanced a step. For if we were asked why the
universal validity of our maxim as a law must be the condition restricting our
actions, and on what we ground the worth which we assign to this manner of
acting- a worth so great that there cannot be any higher interest; and if we
were asked further how it happens that it is by this alone a man believes he
feels his own personal worth, in comparison with which that of an agreeable or
disagreeable condition is to be regarded as nothing, to these questions we could
give no satisfactory answer.
We find indeed sometimes that we can take an interest in a
personal quality which does not involve any interest of external condition,
provided this quality makes us capable of participating in the condition in case
reason were to effect the allotment; that is to say, the mere being worthy of
happiness can interest of itself even without the motive of participating in
this happiness. This judgement, however, is in fact only the effect of the
importance of the moral law which we before presupposed (when by the idea of
freedom we detach ourselves from every empirical interest); but that we ought to
detach ourselves from these interests, i.e., to consider ourselves as free in
action and yet as subject to certain laws, so as to find a worth simply in our
own person which can compensate us for the loss of everything that gives worth
to our condition; this we are not yet able to discern in this way, nor do we see
how it is possible so to act- in other words, whence the moral law derives its
obligation.
It must be freely admitted that there is a sort of circle here
from which it seems impossible to escape. In the order of efficient causes we
assume ourselves free, in order that in the order of ends we may conceive
ourselves as subject to moral laws: and we afterwards conceive ourselves as
subject to these laws, because we have attributed to ourselves freedom of will:
for freedom and self-legislation of will are both autonomy and, therefore, are
reciprocal conceptions, and for this very reason one must not be used to explain
the other or give the reason of it, but at most only logical purposes to reduce
apparently different notions of the same object to one single concept (as we
reduce different fractions of the same value to the lowest terms).
One resource remains to us, namely, to inquire whether we do not
occupy different points of view when by means of freedom we think ourselves as
causes efficient a priori, and when we form our conception of ourselves from our
actions as effects which we see before our eyes.
It is a remark which needs no subtle reflection to make, but
which we may assume that even the commonest understanding can make, although it
be after its fashion by an obscure discernment of judgement which it calls
feeling, that all the "ideas" that come to us involuntarily (as those of the
senses) do not enable us to know objects otherwise than as they affect us; so
that what they may be in themselves remains unknown to us, and consequently that
as regards "ideas" of this kind even with the closest attention and clearness
that the understanding can apply to them, we can by them only attain to the
knowledge of appearances, never to that of things in themselves. As soon as this
distinction has once been made (perhaps merely in consequence of the difference
observed between the ideas given us from without, and in which we are passive,
and those that we produce simply from ourselves, and in which we show our own
activity), then it follows of itself that we must admit and assume behind the
appearance something else that is not an appearance, namely, the things in
themselves; although we must admit that as they can never be known to us except
as they affect us, we can come no nearer to them, nor can we ever know what they
are in themselves. This must furnish a distinction, however crude, between a
world of sense and the world of understanding, of which the former may be
different according to the difference of the sensuous impressions in various
observers, while the second which is its basis always remains the same, Even as
to himself, a man cannot pretend to know what he is in himself from the
knowledge he has by internal sensation. For as he does not as it were create
himself, and does not come by the conception of himself a priori but
empirically, it naturally follows that he can obtain his knowledge even of
himself only by the inner sense and, consequently, only through the appearances
of his nature and the way in which his consciousness is affected. At the same
time beyond these characteristics of his own subject, made up of mere
appearances, he must necessarily suppose something else as their basis, namely,
his ego, whatever its characteristics in itself may be. Thus in respect to mere
perception and receptivity of sensations he must reckon himself as belonging to
the world of sense; but in respect of whatever there may be of pure activity in
him (that which reaches consciousness immediately and not through affecting the
senses), he must reckon himself as belonging to the intellectual world, of
which, however, he has no further knowledge. To such a conclusion the reflecting
man must come with respect to all the things which can be presented to him: it
is probably to be met with even in persons of the commonest understanding, who,
as is well known, are very much inclined to suppose behind the objects of the
senses something else invisible and acting of itself. They spoil it, however, by
presently sensualizing this invisible again; that is to say, wanting to make it
an object of intuition, so that they do not become a whit the wiser.
Now man really finds in himself a faculty by which he
distinguishes himself from everything else, even from himself as affected by
objects, and that is reason. This being pure spontaneity is even elevated above
the understanding. For although the latter is a spontaneity and does not, like
sense, merely contain intuitions that arise when we are affected by things (and
are therefore passive), yet it cannot produce from its activity any other
conceptions than those which merely serve to bring the intuitions of sense under
rules and, thereby, to unite them in one consciousness, and without this use of
the sensibility it could not think at all; whereas, on the contrary, reason
shows so pure a spontaneity in the case of what I call ideas [ideal conceptions]
that it thereby far transcends everything that the sensibility can give it, and
exhibits its most important function in distinguishing the world of sense from
that of understanding, and thereby prescribing the limits of the understanding
itself.
For this reason a rational being must regard himself qua
intelligence (not from the side of his lower faculties) as belonging not to the
world of sense, but to that of understanding; hence he has two points of view
from which he can regard himself, and recognise laws of the exercise of his
faculties, and consequently of all his actions: first, so far as he belongs to
the world of sense, he finds himself subject to laws of nature (heteronomy);
secondly, as belonging to the intelligible world, under laws which being
independent of nature have their foundation not in experience but in reason
alone.
As a rational being, and consequently belonging to the
intelligible world, man can never conceive the causality of his own will
otherwise than on condition of the idea of freedom, for independence of the
determinate causes of the sensible world (an independence which reason must
always ascribe to itself) is freedom. Now the idea of freedom is inseparably
connected with the conception of autonomy, and this again with the universal
principle of morality which is ideally the foundation of all actions of rational
beings, just as the law of nature is of all phenomena.
Now the suspicion is removed which we raised above, that there
was a latent circle involved in our reasoning from freedom to autonomy, and from
this to the moral law, viz.: that we laid down the idea of freedom because of
the moral law only that we might afterwards in turn infer the latter from
freedom, and that consequently we could assign no reason at all for this law,
but could only [present] it as a petitio principii which well disposed minds
would gladly concede to us, but which we could never put forward as a provable
proposition. For now we see that, when we conceive ourselves as free, we
transfer ourselves into the world of understanding as members of it and
recognise the autonomy of the will with its consequence, morality; whereas, if
we conceive ourselves as under obligation, we consider ourselves as belonging to
the world of sense and at the same time to the world of understanding.
How is a Categorical Imperative
Possible?
Every rational being reckons himself qua
intelligence as belonging to the world of understanding, and it is simply as an
efficient cause belonging to that world that he calls his causality a will. On
the other side he is also conscious of himself as a part of the world of sense
in which his actions, which are mere appearances [phenomena] of that causality,
are displayed; we cannot, however, discern how they are possible from this
causality which we do not know; but instead of that, these actions as belonging
to the sensible world must be viewed as determined by other phenomena, namely,
desires and inclinations. If therefore I were only a member of the world of
understanding, then all my actions would perfectly conform to the principle of
autonomy of the pure will; if I were only a part of the world of sense, they
would necessarily be assumed to conform wholly to the natural law of desires and
inclinations, in other words, to the heteronomy of nature. (The former would
rest on morality as the supreme principle, the latter on happiness.) Since,
however, the world of understanding contains the foundation of the world of
sense, and consequently of its laws also, and accordingly gives the law to my
will (which belongs wholly to the world of understanding) directly, and must be
conceived as doing so, it follows that, although on the one side I must regard
myself as a being belonging to the world of sense, yet on the other side I must
recognize myself as subject as an intelligence to the law of the world of
understanding, i.e., to reason, which contains this law in the idea of freedom,
and therefore as subject to the autonomy of the will: consequently I must regard
the laws of the world of understanding as imperatives for me and the actions
which conform to them as duties.
And thus what makes categorical imperatives possible is this,
that the idea of freedom makes me a member of an intelligible world, in
consequence of which, if I were nothing else, all my actions would always
conform to the autonomy of the will; but as I at the same time intuite myself as
a member of the world of sense, they ought so to conform, and this categorical
"ought" implies a synthetic a priori proposition, inasmuch as besides my will as
affected by sensible desires there is added further the idea of the same will
but as belonging to the world of the understanding, pure and practical of
itself, which contains the supreme condition according to reason of the former
will; precisely as to the intuitions of sense there are added concepts of the
understanding which of themselves signify nothing but regular form in general
and in this way synthetic a priori propositions become possible, on which all
knowledge of physical nature rests.
The practical use of common human reason confirms this
reasoning. There is no one, not even the most consummate villain, provided only
that he is otherwise accustomed to the use of reason, who, when we set before
him examples of honesty of purpose, of steadfastness in following good maxims,
of sympathy and general benevolence (even combined with great sacrifices of
advantages and comfort), does not wish that he might also possess these
qualities. Only on account of his inclinations and impulses he cannot attain
this in himself, but at the same time he wishes to be free from such
inclinations which are burdensome to himself. He proves by this that he
transfers himself in thought with a will free from the impulses of the
sensibility into an order of things wholly different from that of his desires in
the field of the sensibility; since he cannot expect to obtain by that wish any
gratification of his desires, nor any position which would satisfy any of his
actual or supposable inclinations (for this would destroy the pre-eminence of
the very idea which wrests that wish from him): he can only expect a greater
intrinsic worth of his own person. This better person, however, he imagines
himself to be when be transfers himself to the point of view of a member of the
world of the understanding, to which he is involuntarily forced by the idea of
freedom, i.e., of independence on determining causes of the world of sense; and
from this point of view he is conscious of a good will, which by his own
confession constitutes the law for the bad will that he possesses as a member of
the world of sense- a law whose authority he recognizes while transgressing it.
What he morally "ought" is then what he necessarily "would," as a member of the
world of the understanding, and is conceived by him as an "ought" only inasmuch
as he likewise considers himself as a member of the world of sense.
Of the Extreme Limits of all Practical
Philosophy.
All men attribute to themselves freedom
of will. Hence come all judgements upon actions as being such as ought to have
been done, although they have not been done. However, this freedom is not a
conception of experience, nor can it be so, since it still remains, even though
experience shows the contrary of what on supposition of freedom are conceived as
its necessary consequences. On the other side it is equally necessary that
everything that takes place should be fixedly determined according to laws of
nature. This necessity of nature is likewise not an empirical conception, just
for this reason, that it involves the motion of necessity and consequently of a
priori cognition. But this conception of a system of nature is confirmed by
experience; and it must even be inevitably presupposed if experience itself is
to be possible, that is, a connected knowledge of the objects of sense resting
on general laws. Therefore freedom is only an idea of reason, and its objective
reality in itself is doubtful; while nature is a concept of the understanding
which proves, and must necessarily prove, its reality in examples of experience.
There arises from this a dialectic of reason, since the freedom
attributed to the will appears to contradict the necessity of nature, and placed
between these two ways reason for speculative purposes finds the road of
physical necessity much more beaten and more appropriate than that of freedom;
yet for practical purposes the narrow footpath of freedom is the only one on
which it is possible to make use of reason in our conduct; hence it is just as
impossible for the subtlest philosophy as for the commonest reason of men to
argue away freedom. Philosophy must then assume that no real contradiction will
be found between freedom and physical necessity of the same human actions, for
it cannot give up the conception of nature any more than that of freedom.
Nevertheless, even though we should never be able to comprehend
how freedom is possible, we must at least remove this apparent contradiction in
a convincing manner. For if the thought of freedom contradicts either itself or
nature, which is equally necessary, it must in competition with physical
necessity be entirely given up.
It would, however, be impossible to escape this contradiction if
the thinking subject, which seems to itself free, conceived itself in the same
sense or in the very same relation when it calls itself free as when in respect
of the same action it assumes itself to be subject to the law of nature. Hence
it is an indispensable problem of speculative philosophy to show that its
illusion respecting the contradiction rests on this, that we think of man in a
different sense and relation when we call him free and when we regard him as
subject to the laws of nature as being part and parcel of nature. It must
therefore show that not only can both these very well co-exist, but that both
must be thought as necessarily united in the same subject, since otherwise no
reason could be given why we should burden reason with an idea which, though it
may possibly without contradiction be reconciled with another that is
sufficiently established, yet entangles us in a perplexity which sorely
embarrasses reason in its theoretic employment. This duty, however, belongs only
to speculative philosophy. The philosopher then has no option whether he will
remove the apparent contradiction or leave it untouched; for in the latter case
the theory respecting this would be bonum vacans, into the possession of which
the fatalist would have a right to enter and chase all morality out of its
supposed domain as occupying it without title.
We cannot however as yet say that we are touching the bounds of
practical philosophy. For the settlement of that controversy does not belong to
it; it only demands from speculative reason that it should put an end to the
discord in which it entangles itself in theoretical questions, so that practical
reason may have rest and security from external attacks which might make the
ground debatable on which it desires to build.
The claims to freedom of will made even by common reason are
founded on the consciousness and the admitted supposition that reason is
independent of merely subjectively determined causes which together constitute
what belongs to sensation only and which consequently come under the general
designation of sensibility. Man considering himself in this way as an
intelligence places himself thereby in a different order of things and in a
relation to determining grounds of a wholly different kind when on the one hand
he thinks of himself as an intelligence endowed with a will, and consequently
with causality, and when on the other he perceives himself as a phenomenon in
the world of sense (as he really is also), and affirms that his causality is
subject to external determination according to laws of nature. Now he soon
becomes aware that both can hold good, nay, must hold good at the same time. For
there is not the smallest contradiction in saying that a thing in appearance
(belonging to the world of sense) is subject to certain laws, of which the very
same as a thing or being in itself is independent, and that he must conceive and
think of himself in this twofold way, rests as to the first on the consciousness
of himself as an object affected through the senses, and as to the second on the
consciousness of himself as an intelligence, i.e., as independent on sensible
impressions in the employment of his reason (in other words as belonging to the
world of understanding).
Hence it comes to pass that man claims the possession of a will
which takes no account of anything that comes under the head of desires and
inclinations and, on the contrary, conceives actions as possible to him, nay,
even as necessary which can only be done by disregarding all desires and
sensible inclinations. The causality of such actions lies in him as an
intelligence and in the laws of effects and actions [which depend] on the
principles of an intelligible world, of which indeed he knows nothing more than
that in it pure reason alone independent of sensibility gives the law; moreover
since it is only in that world, as an intelligence, that he is his proper self
(being as man only the appearance of himself), those laws apply to him directly
and categorically, so that the incitements of inclinations and appetites (in
other words the whole nature of the world of sense) cannot impair the laws of
his volition as an intelligence. Nay, he does not even hold himself responsible
for the former or ascribe them to his proper self, i.e., his will: he only
ascribes to his will any indulgence which he might yield them if he allowed them
to influence his maxims to the prejudice of the rational laws of the will.
When practical reason thinks itself into a world of
understanding, it does not thereby transcend its own limits, as it would if it
tried to enter it by intuition or sensation. The former is only a negative
thought in respect of the world of sense, which does not give any laws to reason
in determining the will and is positive only in this single point that this
freedom as a negative characteristic is at the same time conjoined with a
(positive) faculty and even with a causality of reason, which we designate a
will, namely a faculty of so acting that the principle of the actions shall
conform to the essential character of a rational motive, i.e., the condition
that the maxim have universal validity as a law. But were it to borrow an object
of will, that is, a motive, from the world of understanding, then it would
overstep its bounds and pretend to be acquainted with something of which it
knows nothing. The conception of a world of the understanding is then only a
point of view which reason finds itself compelled to take outside the
appearances in order to conceive itself as practical, which would not be
possible if the influences of the sensibility had a determining power on man,
but which is necessary unless he is to be denied the consciousness of himself as
an intelligence and, consequently, as a rational cause, energizing by reason,
that is, operating freely. This thought certainly involves the idea of an order
and a system of laws different from that of the mechanism of nature which
belongs to the sensible world; and it makes the conception of an intelligible
world necessary (that is to say, the whole system of rational beings as things
in themselves). But it does not in the least authorize us to think of it further
than as to its formal condition only, that is, the universality of the maxims of
the will as laws, and consequently the autonomy of the latter, which alone is
consistent with its freedom; whereas, on the contrary, all laws that refer to a
definite object give heteronomy, which only belongs to laws of nature and can
only apply to the sensible world.
But reason would overstep all its bounds if it undertook to
explain how pure reason can be practical, which would be exactly the same
problem as to explain how freedom is possible.
For we can explain nothing but that which we can reduce to laws,
the object of which can be given in some possible experience. But freedom is a
mere idea, the objective reality of which can in no wise be shown according to
laws of nature, and consequently not in any possible experience; and for this
reason it can never be comprehended or understood, because we cannot support it
by any sort of example or analogy. It holds good only as a necessary hypothesis
of reason in a being that believes itself conscious of a will, that is, of a
faculty distinct from mere desire (namely, a faculty of determining itself to
action as an intelligence, in other words, by laws of reason independently on
natural instincts). Now where determination according to laws of nature ceases,
there all explanation ceases also, and nothing remains but defence, i.e., the
removal of the objections of those who pretend to have seen deeper into the
nature of things, and thereupon boldly declare freedom impossible. We can only
point out to them that the supposed contradiction that they have discovered in
it arises only from this, that in order to be able to apply the law of nature to
human actions, they must necessarily consider man as an appearance: then when we
demand of them that they should also think of him qua intelligence as a thing in
itself, they still persist in considering him in this respect also as an
appearance. In this view it would no doubt be a contradiction to suppose the
causality of the same subject (that is, his will) to be withdrawn from all the
natural laws of the sensible world. But this contradiction disappears, if they
would only bethink themselves and admit, as is reasonable, that behind the
appearances there must also lie at their root (although hidden) the things in
themselves, and that we cannot expect the laws of these to be the same as those
that govern their appearances.
The subjective impossibility of explaining the freedom of the
will is identical with the impossibility of discovering and explaining an
interest * which man can take in the moral law. Nevertheless he does actually
take an interest in it, the basis of which in us we call the moral feeling,
which some have falsely assigned as the standard of our moral judgement, whereas
it must rather be viewed as the subjective effect that the law exercises on the
will, the objective principle of which is furnished by reason alone.
* Interest is that by which reason
becomes practical, i.e., a cause determining the will. Hence we say of rational
beings only that they take an interest in a thing; irrational beings only feel
sensual appetites. Reason takes a direct interest in action then only when the
universal validity of its maxims is alone sufficient to determine the will. Such
an interest alone is pure. But if it can determine the will only by means of
another object of desire or on the suggestion of a particular feeling of the
subject, then reason takes only an indirect interest in the action, and, as
reason by itself without experience cannot discover either objects of the will
or a special feeling actuating it, this latter interest would only be empirical
and not a pure rational interest. The logical interest of reason (namely, to
extend its insight) is never direct, but presupposes purposes for which reason
is employed.
In order indeed that a rational being
who is also affected through the senses should will what reason alone directs
such beings that they ought to will, it is no doubt requisite that reason should
have a power to infuse a feeling of pleasure or satisfaction in the fulfilment
of duty, that is to say, that it should have a causality by which it determines
the sensibility according to its own principles. But it is quite impossible to
discern, i.e., to make it intelligible a priori, how a mere thought, which
itself contains nothing sensible, can itself produce a sensation of pleasure or
pain; for this is a particular kind of causality of which as of every other
causality we can determine nothing whatever a priori; we must only consult
experience about it. But as this cannot supply us with any relation of cause and
effect except between two objects of experience, whereas in this case, although
indeed the effect produced lies within experience, yet the cause is supposed to
be pure reason acting through mere ideas which offer no object to experience, it
follows that for us men it is quite impossible to explain how and why the
universality of the maxim as a law, that is, morality, interests. This only is
certain, that it is not because it interests us that it has validity for us (for
that would be heteronomy and dependence of practical reason on sensibility,
namely, on a feeling as its principle, in which case it could never give moral
laws), but that it interests us because it is valid for us as men, inasmuch as
it had its source in our will as intelligences, in other words, in our proper
self, and what belongs to mere appearance is necessarily subordinated by reason
to the nature of the thing in itself.
The question then, "How a categorical imperative is possible,"
can be answered to this extent, that we can assign the only hypothesis on which
it is possible, namely, the idea of freedom; and we can also discern the
necessity of this hypothesis, and this is sufficient for the practical exercise
of reason, that is, for the conviction of the validity of this imperative, and
hence of the moral law; but how this hypothesis itself is possible can never be
discerned by any human reason. On the hypothesis, however, that the will of an
intelligence is free, its autonomy, as the essential formal condition of its
determination, is a necessary consequence. Moreover, this freedom of will is not
merely quite possible as a hypothesis (not involving any contradiction to the
principle of physical necessity in the connexion of the phenomena of the
sensible world) as speculative philosophy can show: but further, a rational
being who is conscious of causality through reason, that is to say, of a will
(distinct from desires), must of necessity make it practically, that is, in
idea, the condition of all his voluntary actions. But to explain how pure reason
can be of itself practical without the aid of any spring of action that could be
derived from any other source, i.e., how the mere principle of the universal
validity of all its maxims as laws (which would certainly be the form of a pure
practical reason) can of itself supply a spring, without any matter (object) of
the will in which one could antecedently take any interest; and how it can
produce an interest which would be called purely moral; or in other words, how
pure reason can be practical- to explain this is beyond the power of human
reason, and all the labour and pains of seeking an explanation of it are lost.
It is just the same as if I sought to find out how freedom
itself is possible as the causality of a will. For then I quit the ground of
philosophical explanation, and I have no other to go upon. I might indeed revel
in the world of intelligences which still remains to me, but although I have an
idea of it which is well founded, yet I have not the least knowledge of it, nor
an I ever attain to such knowledge with all the efforts of my natural faculty of
reason. It signifies only a something that remains over when I have eliminated
everything belonging to the world of sense from the actuating principles of my
will, serving merely to keep in bounds the principle of motives taken from the
field of sensibility; fixing its limits and showing that it does not contain all
in all within itself, but that there is more beyond it; but this something more
I know no further. Of pure reason which frames this ideal, there remains after
the abstraction of all matter, i.e., knowledge of objects, nothing but the form,
namely, the practical law of the universality of the maxims, and in conformity
with this conception of reason in reference to a pure world of understanding as
a possible efficient cause, that is a cause determining the will. There must
here be a total absence of springs; unless this idea of an intelligible world is
itself the spring, or that in which reason primarily takes an interest; but to
make this intelligible is precisely the problem that we cannot solve.
Here now is the extreme limit of all moral inquiry, and it is of
great importance to determine it even on this account, in order that reason may
not on the one band, to the prejudice of morals, seek about in the world of
sense for the supreme motive and an interest comprehensible but empirical; and
on the other hand, that it may not impotently flap its wings without being able
to move in the (for it) empty space of transcendent concepts which we call the
intelligible world, and so lose itself amidst chimeras. For the rest, the idea
of a pure world of understanding as a system of all intelligences, and to which
we ourselves as rational beings belong (although we are likewise on the other
side members of the sensible world), this remains always a useful and legitimate
idea for the purposes of rational belief, although all knowledge stops at its
threshold, useful, namely, to produce in us a lively interest in the moral law
by means of the noble ideal of a universal kingdom of ends in themselves
(rational beings), to which we can belong as members then only when we carefully
conduct ourselves according to the maxims of freedom as if they were laws of
nature.
Concluding Remark
The speculative employment of reason
with respect to nature leads to the absolute necessity of some supreme cause of
the world: the practical employment of reason with a view to freedom leads also
to absolute necessity, but only of the laws of the actions of a rational being
as such. Now it is an essential principle of reason, however employed, to push
its knowledge to a consciousness of its necessity (without which it would not be
rational knowledge). It is, however, an equally essential restriction of the
same reason that it can neither discern the necessity of what is or what
happens, nor of what ought to happen, unless a condition is supposed on which it
is or happens or ought to happen. In this way, however, by the constant inquiry
for the condition, the satisfaction of reason is only further and further
postponed. Hence it unceasingly seeks the unconditionally necessary and finds
itself forced to assume it, although without any means of making it
comprehensible to itself, happy enough if only it can discover a conception
which agrees with this assumption. It is therefore no fault in our deduction of
the supreme principle of morality, but an objection that should be made to human
reason in general, that it cannot enable us to conceive the absolute necessity
of an unconditional practical law (such as the categorical imperative must be).
It cannot be blamed for refusing to explain this necessity by a condition, that
is to say, by means of some interest assumed as a basis, since the law would
then cease to be a supreme law of reason. And thus while we do not comprehend
the practical unconditional necessity of the moral imperative, we yet comprehend
its incomprehensibility, and this is all that can be fairly demanded of a
philosophy which strives to carry its principles up to the very limit of human
reason.
THE END