Western philosophy
History of Western philosophy from its development among the ancient
Greeks to the present.
Medieval philosophy
Medieval philosophy » The late Middle Ages
In the late Middle Ages earlier ways of philosophizing were continued
and formalized into distinct schools of thought. In the Dominican order,
Thomism, the theological and philosophical system of Thomas Aquinas, was
made the official teaching, though the Dominicans did not always adhere
to it rigorously. Averroism, cultivated by philosophers such as John of
Jandun (c. 1286–1328), remained a significant, though sterile, movement
into the Renaissance. In the Franciscan order, John Duns Scotus (c.
1266–1308) and William of Ockham (c. 1285–c. 1347) developed new styles
of theology and philosophy that vied with Thomism throughout the late
Middle Ages.

|
John of Jandun
French philosopher
French Jean De Jandun
born c. 1286, Jandun, Champagne, Fr.
died 1328, Todi, Papal States
Main
foremost 14th-century interpreter of Averroës’ rendering of
Aristotle.
After study at the University of Paris, John became
master of arts at the Collège de Navarre in Paris, where he
lectured on Aristotle. He associated with Marsilius of
Padua, writer of the Defensor Pacis, which asserted the
superiority of civil authority over that of the pope.
Because of controversy over this work, John and Marsilius
sought the protection of Louis IV of Bavaria. After a series
of condemnatory papal bulls, they were excommunicated as
heretics by Pope John XXII in 1327.
John of Jandun’s most influential writings are
commentaries on Aristotle; his major concern was the
division between faith and reason. Some critics think that
he held a “double-truth” theory, believing that
contradictory statements of faith and reason may be
simultaneously true; others call him anti-Christian, and
still others judge him to be a thinker of the Augustinian
tradition.
|
Medieval philosophy » The late Middle Ages » John Duns Scotus
John Duns Scotus opposed the rationalists’ contention that philosophy is
self-sufficient and adequate to satisfy the human desire for knowledge.
In fact, he claimed that a pure philosopher, such as Aristotle, could
not truly understand the human condition because he was ignorant of the
Fall of Man and his need for grace and redemption. Unenlightened by
Christian revelation, Aristotle mistook humankind’s present fallen
state, in which all knowledge comes through the senses, for its natural
condition, in which the object of knowledge would be coextensive with
all being, including the being of God. The limitation of Aristotle’s
philosophy was apparent to Duns Scotus in the Aristotelian proof of the
existence of God as the primary mover of the universe. More adequate
than this physical proof, he contended, is his own very intricate
metaphysical demonstration of the existence of God as the absolutely
primary, unique, and infinite being. He incorporated the Anselmian
argument into this demonstration. For Duns Scotus, the notion of
infinite being, not that of primary mover or being itself, is
humankind’s most perfect concept of God.
In opposition to the Greco-Arabic view of the government of the
universe from above by necessary causes, Duns Scotus stressed the
contingency of the universe and its total dependence on God’s infinite
creative will. He adopted the traditional Franciscan voluntarism,
elevating the will above the intellect in human beings.
Duns Scotus’s doctrine of universals justly earned him the title
“Doctor Subtilis.” Universals, in his view, exist only as abstract
concepts, but they are based on common natures, such as humanity, which
exist, or can exist, in many individuals. Common natures are real, and
they have a real unity of their own distinct from the unity of the
individuals in which they exist. The individuality of each individual is
due to an added positive reality that makes the common nature a specific
individual—e.g., Socrates. Duns Scotus calls such a reality an
“individual difference,” or “thisness” (haecceitas). It is an original
development of the earlier medieval realism of universals.

|
John Duns Scotus
Scottish philosopher and theologian
Latin given name Joannes, byname Doctor Subtilis
born c. 1266, Duns, Lothian [now in Scottish Borders],
Scotland
died November 8, 1308, Cologne [Germany]
Main
influential Franciscan realist philosopher and scholastic
theologian who pioneered the classical defense of the
doctrine that Mary, the mother of Jesus, was conceived
without original sin (the Immaculate Conception). He also
argued that the Incarnation was not dependent on the fact
that man had sinned, that will is superior to intellect and
love to knowledge, and that the essence of heaven consists
in beatific love rather than the vision of God.
Early life and career
As the historian Ernest Renan noted, there is perhaps no
other great medieval thinker whose life is as little known
as that of Duns Scotus. Yet patient research during the 20th
century has unearthed a number of facts. Early 14th-century
manuscripts, for instance, state explicitly that John Duns
was a Scot, from Duns, who belonged to the English province
of Friars Minor (the order founded by Francis of Assisi),
that “he flourished at Cambridge, Oxford, and Paris and died
in Cologne.”
Though accounts of his early schooling and entry into the
Franciscan Order are unreliable, Duns Scotus would have
learned as a novice of St. Francis’s personal love for
Christ in the Eucharist, his reverence for the priesthood,
and his loyalty to “the Lord Pope”—themes given special
emphasis in Duns Scotus’s own theology. In addition, he
would have studied interpretations of St. Francis’s thought,
particularly those of St. Bonaventure, who saw the
Franciscan ideal as a striving for God through learning that
will culminate in a mystical union of love. In his early
Lectura Oxoniensis, Duns Scotus insisted that theology is
not a speculative but a practical science of God and that
man’s ultimate goal is union with the divine Trinity through
love. Though this union is known only by divine revelation,
philosophy can prove the existence of an infinite being, and
herein lies its merit and service to theology. Duns Scotus’s
own intellectual journey to God is to be found in his
prayerful Tractatus de primo principio (A Treatise on God As
First Principle, 1966), perhaps his last work.
Jurisdictionally, the Scots belonged to the Franciscan
province of England, whose principal house of studies was at
the University of Oxford, where Duns Scotus apparently spent
13 years (1288–1301) preparing for inception as master of
theology. There is no record of where he took the eight
years of preliminary philosophical training (four for a
bachelor’s and four for the master’s degrees) required to
enter such a program.
After studying theology for almost four years, John Duns
was ordained priest by Oliver Sutton, bishop of Lincoln (the
diocese to which Oxford belonged). Records show the event
took place at St. Andrew’s Church in Northampton on March
17, 1291. In view of the minimum age requirements for the
priesthood, this suggests that Duns Scotus must have been
born no later than March 1266, certainly not in 1274 or 1275
as earlier historians maintained.
Duns Scotus would have spent the last four years of the
13-year program as bachelor of theology, devoting the first
year to preparing lectures on Peter Lombard’s Sentences—the
textbook of theology in the medieval universities—and the
second to delivering them. A bachelor’s role at this stage
was not to give a literal explanation of this work but
rather to pose and solve questions of his own on topics that
paralleled subject “distinctions” in Lombard. Consequently,
the questions Duns Scotus discussed in his Lectura
Oxoniensis ranged over the whole field of theology. When he
had finished, he began to revise and enlarge them with a
view to publication. Such a revised version was called an
ordinatio, in contrast to his original notes (lectura) or a
student report (reportatio) of the actual lecture. If such a
report was corrected by the lecturer himself, it became a
reportatio examinata. From a date mentioned in the prologue,
it is clear that in 1300 Duns Scotus was already at work on
his monumental Oxford commentary on the Sentences, known as
the Ordinatio or Opus Oxoniense.
Statutes of the university required that the third year
be devoted to lectures on the Bible; and, in the final year,
the bachelor formatus, as he was called, had to take part in
public disputations under different masters, including his
own. In Duns Scotus’s case, this last year can be dated
rather precisely, for his name occurs among the 22 Oxford
Franciscans, including the two masters of theology, Adam of
Howden and Philip of Bridlington, who were presented to
Bishop Dalderby on July 26, 1300, for faculties, or the
proper permissions to hear confessions of the great crowds
that thronged to the Franciscans’ church in the city.
Because the friars had but one chair of theology and the
list of trained bachelors waiting to incept was long, regent
masters were replaced annually. Adam was the 28th and Philip
the 29th Oxford master, so that Philip’s year of regency was
just beginning. It must have coincided with Duns Scotus’s
final and 13th year because an extant disputation of
Bridlington as master indicates John Duns was the bachelor
respondent. This means that by June of 1301 he had completed
all the requirements for the mastership in theology; yet, in
view of the long line ahead of him, there was little hope of
incepting as master at Oxford for perhaps a decade to come.
Years at the University of Paris
When the turn came for the English province to provide a
talented candidate for the Franciscan chair of theology at
the more prestigious University of Paris, Duns Scotus was
appointed. One reportatio of his Paris lectures indicates
that he began commenting on the Sentences there in the
autumn of 1302 and continued to June 1303. Before the term
ended, however, the university was affected by the
long-smouldering feud between King Philip IV and Pope
Boniface VIII. The issue was taxation of church property to
support the king’s wars with England. When Boniface
excommunicated him, the monarch retaliated by calling for a
general church council to depose the pope. He won over the
French clergy and the university. On June 24, 1303, a great
antipapal demonstration took place. Friars paraded in the
Paris streets. Berthold of Saint-Denis, bishop of Orleans
and former chancellor of the university, together with two
Dominicans and two Franciscans, addressed the meeting. On
the following day royal commissioners examined each member
of the Franciscan house to determine whether he was with or
against the king. Some 70 friars, mostly French, sided with
Philip, while the rest (some 80 odd) remained loyal to the
pope, among them John Duns Scotus and Master Gonsalvus
Hispanus. The penalty was exile from France within three
days. Boniface countered with a bull of August 15 suspending
the university’s right to give degrees in theology or canon
and civil law. As a result of his harassment and
imprisonment by the king’s minister, however, Boniface died
in October and was succeeded by Pope Benedict XI. In the
interests of peace, Benedict lifted the ban against the
university in April 1304, and shortly afterwards the king
facilitated the return of students.
Where Duns Scotus spent the exile is unclear. Possibly
his Cambridge lectures stem from this period, although they
may have been given during the academic year of 1301–02
before coming to Paris. At any rate, Duns Scotus was back
before the summer of 1304, for he was the bachelor
respondent in the disputatio in aula (“public disputation”)
when his predecessor, Giles of Ligny, was promoted to
master. On November 18 of that same year, Gonsalvus, who had
been elected minister general of the Franciscan order at the
Pentecost chapter, or meeting, assigned as Giles’s successor
“Friar John Scotus, of whose laudable life, excellent
knowledge, and most subtle ability as well as his other
remarkable qualities I am fully informed, partly from long
experience, partly from report which has spread everywhere.”
The period following Duns Scotus’s inception as master in
1305 was one of great literary activity. Aided by a staff of
associates and secretaries, he set to work to complete his
Ordinatio begun at Oxford, using not only the Oxford and
Cambridge lectures but also those of Paris. A search of
manuscripts reveals a magisterial dispute Duns Scotus
conducted with the Dominican master, Guillaume Pierre Godin,
against the thesis that matter is the principle of
individuation (the metaphysical principle that makes an
individual thing different from other things of the same
species), but so far no questions publicly disputed
ordinarie—i.e., in regular turn with the other regent
masters—have been discovered. There is strong evidence,
however, that some questions of this sort existed but were
eventually incorporated into the Ordinatio. Duns Scotus did
conduct one solemn quodlibetal disputation, so called
because the master accepted questions on any topic (de
quodlibet) and from any bachelor or master present (a
quodlibet). The 21 questions Duns Scotus treated were later
revised, enlarged, and organized under two main topics, God
and creatures. Though less extensive in scope than the
Ordinatio, these Quaestiones quodlibetales are scarcely less
important because they represent his most mature thinking.
Indeed, Duns Scotus’s renown depends principally on these
two major works.
The short but important Tractatus de primo principio, a
compendium of what reason can prove about God, draws heavily
upon the Ordinatio. The remaining authentic works seem to
represent questions discussed privately for the benefit of
the Franciscan student philosophers or theologians. They
include, in addition to the Collationes (from both Oxford
and Paris), the Quaestiones in Metaphysicam Aristotelis and
a series of logical questions occasioned by the Neoplatonist
Porphyry’s Isagoge and Aristotle’s De praedicamentis, De
interpretatione, and De sophisticis elenchis. These works
certainly postdate the Oxford Lectura and may even belong to
the Parisian period. Antonius Andreus, an early follower who
studied under Duns Scotus at Paris, expressly says his own
commentaries on Porphyry and De praedicamentis are culled
from statements of Duns Scotus sedentis super cathedram
magistralem (“sitting on the master’s chair”).
Final period at Cologne
In 1307 Duns Scotus was appointed professor at Cologne. Some
have suggested that Gonsalvus sent Scotus to Cologne for his
own safety. His controversial claim that Mary need never
have contracted original sin seemed to conflict with the
doctrine of Christ’s universal redemption. Duns Scotus’s
effort was to show that the perfect mediation would be
preventative, not merely curative. Though his brilliant
defense of the Immaculate Conception marked the turning
point in the history of the doctrine, it was immediately
challenged by secular and Dominican colleagues. When the
question arose in a solemn quodlibetal disputation, the
secular master Jean de Pouilly, for example, declared the
Scotist thesis not only improbable but even heretical.
Should anyone be so presumptuous as to assert it, he argued
impassionedly, one should proceed against him “not with
arguments but otherwise.” At a time when Philip IV had
initiated heresy trials against the wealthy Knights
Templars, Pouilly’s words have an ominous ring. There seems
to have been something hasty about Duns Scotus’s departure
in any case. Writing a century later, the Scotist William of
Vaurouillon referred to the traditional account that Duns
Scotus received the minister general’s letter while walking
with his students and set out at once for Cologne, taking
little or nothing with him. Duns Scotus lectured at Cologne
until his death. His body at present lies in the nave of the
Franciscan church near the Cologne cathedral, and in many
places he is venerated as blessed.
Whatever the reason for his abrupt departure from Paris,
Duns Scotus certainly left his Ordinatio and Quodlibet
unfinished. Eager pupils completed the works, substituting
materials from reportationes examinatae for the questions
Duns Scotus left undictated. The critical Vatican edition
begun in 1950 is aimed at, among other things,
reconstructing the Ordinatio as Duns Scotus left it, with
all his corrigenda, or corrections.
Despite their imperfect form, Duns Scotus’s works were
widely circulated. His claim that universal concepts are
based on a “common nature” in individuals was one of the
central issues in the 14th-century controversy between
Realists and Nominalists concerning the question of whether
general types are figments of the mind or are real. Later
this same Scotist principle deeply influenced Charles
Sanders Peirce, an American philosopher, who considered Duns
Scotus the greatest speculative mind of the Middle Ages as
well as one of the “profoundest metaphysicians that ever
lived.” His strong defense of the papacy against the divine
right of kings made him unpopular with the English Reformers
of the 16th century, for whom “dunce” (a Dunsman) became a
word of obloquy, yet his theory of intuitive cognition
suggested to John Calvin, the Genevan Reformer, how God may
be “experienced.” During the 16th to 18th centuries among
Catholic theologians, Duns Scotus’s following rivaled that
of Thomas Aquinas and in the 17th century outnumbered that
of all the other schools combined.
The Rev. Allan Bernard Wolter, O.F.M.
|
Medieval philosophy » The late Middle Ages » William of Ockham
In the late 14th century, Thomism and Scotism were called the “old way”
(via antiqua) of philosophizing, in contrast to the “modern way” (via
moderna) begun by philosophers such as William of Ockham. Ockham, no
less than Duns Scotus, wanted to defend the Christian doctrine of the
freedom and omnipotence of God and the contingency of creatures against
the necessitarianism of Greco-Arabic philosophy. But for him the freedom
of God is incompatible with the existence of divine ideas as positive
models of creation. God does not use preconceived ideas when he creates,
as Duns Scotus maintained, but he fashions the universe as he wishes. As
a result, creatures have no natures, or essences, in common. There are
no realities but individual things, and these have nothing in common.
They are more or less like each other, however, and on this basis human
beings can form universal concepts of them and talk about them in
general terms.
The absolute freedom of God was often used by Ockham as a principle
of philosophical and theological explanation. Because the order of
nature has been freely created by God, it could have been different:
fire, for example, could cool as it now heats. If God wishes, he can
give us the sight, or “intuitive knowledge,” of a star without the
reality of the star. The moral order could also have been different. God
could have made hating him meritorious instead of loving him. It was
typical of Ockham not to put too much trust in the power of human reason
to reach the truth. For him, philosophy must often be content with
probable arguments, as in establishing the existence of the Christian
God. Faith alone gives certitude in this and in other vital matters.
Another principle invoked by Ockham is that a plurality is not to be
posited without necessity. This principle of economy of thought, later
stated as “beings are not to be multiplied without necessity,” is called
“Ockham’s razor.”
Ockhamism was censured by a papal commission at Avignon in 1326, and
in 1474 it was forbidden to be taught at Paris. Nevertheless, it spread
widely in the late Middle Ages and rivaled Thomism and Scotism in
popularity. Other Scholastics in the 14th century shared Ockham’s basic
principles and contributed with him to skepticism and probabilism in
philosophy. John of Mirecourt (flourished 14th century) stressed the
absolute power of God and the divine will to the point of making God the
cause of human sin. Nicholas of Autrecourt (c. 1300–c. 1350) adopted a
skeptical attitude regarding matters such as the ability of human beings
to prove the existence of God and the reality of substance and
causality. Rejecting Aristotelianism as inimical to the Christian faith,
he advocated a return to the atomism of the ancient Greeks as a more
adequate explanation of the universe.

|
William of Ockham
English philosopher
also called William Ockham, Ockham also spelled Occam,
byname Venerabilis Inceptor (Latin: “Venerable
Enterpriser”), or Doctor Invincibilis (“Invincible Doctor”)
born c. 1285, Ockham, Surrey?, Eng.
died 1347/49, Munich, Bavaria [now in Germany]
Main
Franciscan philosopher, theologian, and political writer, a
late scholastic thinker regarded as the founder of a form of
nominalism—the school of thought that denies that universal
concepts such as “father” have any reality apart from the
individual things signified by the universal or general
term.
Early life
Little is known of Ockham’s childhood. It seems that he was
still a youngster when he entered the Franciscan order. At
that time a central issue of concern in the order and a main
topic of debate in the church was the interpretation of the
rule of life composed by St. Francis of Assisi concerning
the strictness of the poverty that should be practiced
within the order. Ockham’s early schooling in a Franciscan
convent concentrated on the study of logic; throughout his
career, his interest in logic never waned, because he
regarded the science of terms as fundamental and
indispensable for practicing all the sciences of things,
including God, the world, and ecclesiastical or civil
institutions; in all his disputes logic was destined to
serve as his chief weapon against adversaries.
After his early training, Ockham took the traditional
course of theological studies at the University of Oxford
and apparently between 1317 and 1319 lectured on the
Sentences of Peter Lombard—a 12th-century theologian whose
work was the official textbook of theology in the
universities until the 16th century. His lectures were also
set down in written commentaries, of which the commentary on
Book I of the Sentences (a commentary known as Ordinatio)
was actually written by Ockham himself. His opinions aroused
strong opposition from members of the theological faculty of
Oxford, however, and he left the university without
obtaining his master’s degree in theology. Ockham thus
remained, academically speaking, an undergraduate—known as
an inceptor (“beginner”) in Oxonian language or, to use a
Parisian equivalent, a baccalaureus formatus.
Ockham continued his academic career, apparently in
English convents, simultaneously studying points of logic in
natural philosophy and participating in theological debates.
When he left his country for Avignon, Fr., in the autumn of
1324 at the pope’s request, he was acquainted with a
university environment shaken not only by disputes but also
by the challenging of authority: that of the bishops in
doctrinal matters and that of the chancellor of the
university, John Lutterell, who was dismissed from his post
in 1322 at the demand of the teaching staff.
However abstract and impersonal the style of Ockham’s
writings may be, they reveal at least two aspects of
Ockham’s intellectual and spiritual attitude: he was a
theologian-logician (theologicus logicus is Luther’s term).
On the one hand, with his passion for logic he insisted on
evaluations that are severely rational, on distinctions
between the necessary and the incidental and differentiation
between evidence and degrees of probability—an insistence
that places great trust in man’s natural reason and his
human nature. On the other hand, as a theologian he referred
to the primary importance of the God of the creed whose
omnipotence determines the gratuitous salvation of men;
God’s saving action consists of giving without any
obligation and is already profusely demonstrated in the
creation of nature. The medieval rule of economy, that
“plurality should not be assumed without necessity,” has
come to be known as “Ockham’s razor”; the principle was used
by Ockham to eliminate many entities that had been devised,
especially by the scholastic philosophers, to explain
reality.
Treatise to John XXII
Ockham met John Lutterell again at Avignon; in a treatise
addressed to Pope John XXII, the former chancellor of Oxford
denounced Ockham’s teaching on the Sentences, extracting
from it 56 propositions that he showed to be in serious
error. Lutterell then became a member of a committee of six
theologians that produced two successive reports based on
extracts from Ockham’s commentary, of which the second was
more severely critical. Ockham, however, presented to the
pope another copy of the Ordinatio in which he had made some
corrections. It appeared that he would be condemned for his
teaching, but the condemnation never came.
At the convent where he resided in Avignon, Ockham met
Bonagratia of Bergamo, a doctor of civil and canon law who
was being persecuted for his opposition to John XXII on the
problem of Franciscan poverty. On Dec. 1, 1327, the
Franciscan general Michael of Cesena arrived in Avignon and
stayed at the same convent; he, too, had been summoned by
the pope in connection with the dispute over the holding of
property. They were at odds over the theoretical problem of
whether Christ and his Apostles had owned the goods they
used; that is, whether they had renounced all ownership
(both private and corporate), the right of property and the
right to the use of property. Michael maintained that
because Christ and his Apostles had renounced all ownership
and all rights to property, the Franciscans were justified
in attempting to do the same thing.
The relations between John and Michael grew steadily
worse, to such an extent that, on May 26, 1328, Michael fled
from Avignon accompanied by Bonagratia and William. Ockham,
who was already a witness in an appeal secretly drafted by
Michael on April 13, publicly endorsed the appeal in
September at Pisa, where the three Franciscans were staying
under the protection of Emperor Louis IV the Bavarian, who
had been excommunicated in 1324 and proclaimed by John XXII
to have forfeited all rights to the empire. They followed
him to Munich in 1330, and thereafter Ockham wrote fervently
against the papacy in defense of both the strict Franciscan
notion of poverty and the empire.
Instructed by his superior general in 1328 to study three
papal bulls on poverty, Ockham found that they contained
many errors that showed John XXII to be a heretic who had
forfeited his mandate by reason of his heresy. His status of
pseudo-pope was confirmed in Ockham’s view in 1330–31 by his
sermons proposing that the souls of the saved did not enjoy
the vision of God immediately after death but only after
they were rejoined with the body at the Last Judgment, an
opinion that contradicted tradition and was ultimately
rejected.
Nevertheless, his principal dispute remained the question
of poverty, which he believed was so important for religious
perfection that it required the discipline of a theory:
whoever chooses to live under the evangelical rule of St.
Francis follows in the footsteps of Christ who is God and
therefore king of the universe but who appeared as a poor
man, renouncing the right of ownership, submitting to the
temporal power, and desiring to reign on this earth only
through the faith vested in him. This reign expresses itself
in the form of a church that is organized but has no
infallible authority—either on the part of a pope or a
council—and is essentially a community of the faithful that
has lasted over the centuries and is sure to last for more,
even though temporarily reduced to a few, or even to one;
everyone, regardless of status or sex, has to defend in the
church the faith that is common to all.
For Ockham the power of the pope is limited by the
freedom of Christians that is established by the gospel and
the natural law. It is therefore legitimate and in keeping
with the gospel to side with the empire against the papacy
or to defend, as Ockham did in 1339, the right of the king
of England to tax church property. From 1330 to 1338, in the
heat of this dispute, Ockham wrote 15 or 16 more or less
political works; some of them were written in collaboration,
but Opus nonaginta dierum (“Work of 90 Days”), the most
voluminous, was written alone.
Excommunication
Excommunicated after his flight from Avignon, Ockham
maintained the same basic position after the death of John
XXII in 1334, during the reign of Benedict XII (1334–42),
and after the election of Clement VI. In these final years
he found time to write two treatises on logic, which bear
witness to the leading role that he consistently assigned to
that discipline, and he discussed the submission procedures
proposed to him by Pope Clement. Ockham was long thought to
have died at a convent in Munich in 1349 during the Black
Death, but he may actually have died there in 1347.
Paul D. Vignaux
|
|
|

|
John of Mirecourt
French philosopher
French Jean De Méricour, Latin Johannes De Mercuria
flourished 14th century
Main
French Cistercian monk, philosopher, and theologian whose
skepticism about certitude in human knowledge and whose
limitation of the use of reason in theological statements
established him as a leading exponent of medieval Christian
nominalism (the doctrine that universals are only names with
no basis in reality) and voluntarism (the doctrine that will
and not reason is the dominant factor in experience and in
the constitution of the world).
Originally from the Vosges Mountains in Lorraine, John,
also called “the White Monk” because of his religious
clothing, obtained his bachelor’s degree in theology at
Paris in 1345 and wrote a commentary on the Sentences, or
theological theses, of Peter Lombard. In 1347 the university
faculty censured 63 propositions from this commentary for
their divergence from Roman Catholic orthodoxy. Later that
year, however, following the counsel of Pope Clement VI that
church authority should not involve itself in philosophical
matters not immediately related to matters of faith, the
faculty granted John’s request to submit an accompanying
“apology,” or clarification, with his theological commentary
and then reduced the censure to 41 propositions. John’s
basic proposals were that rational certitude is largely
unattainable because of the fallibility of the senses, and,
even granting the possibility of the human mind’s forming
correct ideas, truth escapes it because God, in his absolute
power, can alter reality. Accordingly, John denied the
possibility of rationally proving the existence of God as
the most perfect of all beings or as the first cause of all
that exists, indeed, even that any created thing requires a
cause. He submitted that it is more meritorious for man to
believe in God’s existence by faith informed with love than
to reach certainty by deductive reasoning.
John, however, admitted the certainty of self-existence,
the doubting of which served only to prove the existence of
a doubting self. His difficulties with church authorities
arose principally from his attributing to God a role in the
existence of evil and suffering, citing that, even if God is
said only to permit evil, he in effect causes it. John’s
extreme views derived from his concern to safeguard at least
a limited area of cognitional certitude, while acknowledging
God’s absolute freedom to effect anything, even the
possibility that man might hate him.
|
|
|

|
Nicholas of Autrecourt
French philosopher and theologian
French Nicolas D’autrecourt
born c. 1300, Autrecourt, near Verdun, Fr.
died after 1350, Metz, Lorrain
Main
French philosopher and theologian known principally for
developing medieval Skepticism to its extreme logical
conclusions, which were condemned as heretical.
Nicholas was an advanced student in liberal arts and
philosophy at the Sorbonne faculty of the University of
Paris from 1320 to 1327. He became one of the most notable
adherents of nominalism, a school of thought holding that
only individual objects are real and that universal concepts
simply express things as names. Nicholas’ chief writings are
commentaries on the 12th-century Sentences of Peter Lombard,
the basic medieval compendium of philosophical theology, and
on the Politics of Aristotle; nine letters to the Franciscan
monk-philosopher Bernard of Arezzo; and an important
treatise usually designated by the opening words Exigit ordo
executionis (“The order of completion requires”). This last
contains the 60 theses controverted at Nicholas’ heresy
trial, convened by Pope Benedict XII at Avignon, in 1340.
Nicholas rejected the traditional Aristotelian
objectivism, with its allusions to a single intellect for
all men, and proposed that there are only two bases for
intellectual certitude: the logical principle of identity,
with its correlative principle of contradiction, which
states that a thing cannot simultaneously be itself and
another; and the immediate evidence of sense data.
Consistent with his nominalist doctrine, he denied that any
causal relation could be known experientially and taught
that the very principle of causality could be reduced to the
empirical declaration of the succession of two facts. The
consequence of such a concept of causality, he averred, was
to reject the possibility of any rational proof for the
existence of God and to deny any divine cause in creation.
Indeed, he held as more probable that the world had existed
from eternity.
Nicholas’ nominalism precluded the possibility of knowing
anything as a permanent concept and allowed only the
conscious experience of an object’s sensible qualities.
Rejecting Scholastic–Aristotelian philosophy and physics,
Nicholas believed that the physical and mental universe is
ultimately composed of simple, indivisible particles or
atoms. He maintained, however, that his innovative thought
did not affect his fidelity to Christian religious
tradition, including the moral commandments and belief in a
future life. Faith and reason, he taught, operate
independently from each other, and one could assent to a
religious doctrine that reason might contradict. Because of
the fallibility of the senses and the human inclination—even
in Aristotle—toward erroneous judgment, evidence and truth
are not always identical, and philosophy at best is simply
the prevalence of the more probable over the less probable.
The ecclesiastical judges at Nicholas’ heresy trial
labeled his avowals of Christian belief as mere subterfuge
and denounced him. Condemned in 1346 by Pope Clement VI,
Nicholas finally was ordered in 1347 to resign his
professorship, recant his error, and publicly burn his
writings. That he took refuge with Emperor Louis IV the
Bavarian is a legend created to form a parallel with the
life of William of Ockham, his nominalist precursor.
Nicholas became dean of the cathedral at Metz in 1350, after
which nothing more is heard of him. His Exigit manuscript
was discovered by A. Birkenmayer at the Bodleian Library,
Oxford, and was published in 1939 by J.R. O’Donnell in
Medieval Studies.
|
Medieval philosophy » The late Middle Ages » Meister Eckehart
The trend away from Aristotelianism was accentuated by the German
Dominican Meister Eckehart (c. 1260–c. 1327), who developed a
speculative mysticism of both Christian and Neoplatonic inspiration.
Eckehart depicted the ascent of the soul to God in Neoplatonic terms: by
gradually purifying itself from the body, the soul transcends being and
knowledge until it is absorbed in the One. The soul is then united with
God at its highest point, or “citadel.” God himself transcends being and
knowledge. Sometimes Eckehart describes God as the being of all things.
This language, which was also used by Erigena and other Christian
Neoplatonists, leaves him open to the charge of pantheism (the doctrine
that the being of creatures is identical with that of God); but for Eckehart there is an infinite gulf between creatures and God. Eckehart
meant that creatures have no existence of their own but are given
existence by God, as the body is made to exist and is contained by the
soul. Eckehart’s profound influence can be seen in the flowering of
mysticism in the German Rhineland in the late Middle Ages.

|
Meister Eckhart
German mystic
English Master Eckhart, original name Johannes Eckhart, also
called Eckhart von Hochheim, Eckhart also spelled Eckehart
born c. 1260, Hochheim?, Thuringia [now in Germany]
died 1327/28?, Avignon, France
Main
Dominican theologian and writer who was the greatest German
speculative mystic. In the transcripts of his sermons in
German and Latin, he charts the course of union between the
individual soul and God.
Johannes Eckhart entered the Dominican order when he was
15 and studied in Cologne, perhaps under the Scholastic
philosopher Albert the Great. The intellectual background
there was influenced by the great Dominican theologian
Thomas Aquinas, who had recently died. In his mid-30s,
Eckhart was nominated vicar (the main Dominican official) of
Thuringia. Before and after this assignment he taught
theology at Saint-Jacques’s priory in Paris. It was also in
Paris that he received a master’s degree (1302) and
consequently was known as Meister Eckhart.
Eckhart wrote four works in German that are usually
called “treatises.” At about the age of 40 he wrote the
Talks of Instruction, on self-denial, the nobility of will
and intellect, and obedience to God. In the same period, he
faced the Franciscans in some famous disputations on
theological issues. In 1303 he became provincial (leader) of
the Dominicans in Saxony, and three years later vicar of
Bohemia. His main activity, especially from 1314, was
preaching to the contemplative nuns established throughout
the Rhine River valley. He resided in Strasbourg as a prior.
The best-attested German work of this middle part of his
life is the Book of Divine Consolation, dedicated to the
Queen of Hungary. The other two treatises were The Nobleman
and On Detachment. The teachings of the mature Eckhart
describe four stages of the union between the soul and God:
dissimilarity, similarity, identity, breakthrough. At the
outset, God is all, the creature is nothing; at the ultimate
stage, “the soul is above God.” The driving power of this
process is detachment.
1. Dissimilarity: “All creatures are pure nothingness. I
do not say they are small or petty: they are pure
nothingness.” Whereas God inherently possesses being,
creatures do not possess being but receive it derivatively.
Outside God, there is pure nothingness. “The being (of
things) is God.” The “noble man” moves among things in
detachment, knowing that they are nothing in themselves and
yet aware that they are full of God—their being.
2. Similarity: Man thus detached from the singular
(individual things) and attached to the universal (Being)
discovers himself to be an image of God. Divine resemblance,
an assimilation, then emerges: the Son, image of the Father,
engenders himself within the detached soul. As an image,
“thou must be in Him and for Him, and not in thee and for
thee.”
3. Identity: Eckhart’s numerous statements on identity
between God and the soul can be easily misunderstood. He
never has substantial identity in mind, but God’s operation
and man’s becoming are considered as one. God is no longer
outside man, but he is perfectly interiorized. Hence such
statements: “The being and the nature of God are mine; Jesus
enters the castle of the soul; the spark in the soul is
beyond time and space; the soul’s light is uncreated and
cannot be created, it takes possession of God with no
mediation; the core of the soul and the core of God are
one.”
4. Breakthrough: To Meister Eckhart, identity with God is
still not enough; to abandon all things without abandoning
God is still not abandoning anything. Man must live “without
why.” He must seek nothing, not even God. Such a thought
leads man into the desert, anterior to God. For Meister
Eckhart, God exists as “God” only when the creature invokes
him. Eckhart calls “Godhead” the origin of all things that
is beyond God (God conceived as Creator). “God and the
Godhead are as distinct as heaven and earth.” The soul is no
longer the Son. The soul is now the Father: it engenders God
as a divine person. “If I were not, God would not be God.”
Detachment thus reaches its conclusion in the breakthrough
beyond God. If properly understood, this idea is genuinely
Christian: it retraces, for the believer, the way of the
Cross of Christ.
These teachings are to be found in his Latin works too.
But the Latin Sermons, Commentaries on the Bible, and
Fragments are more Scholastic and do not reveal the
originality of his thought. Nevertheless, Eckhart enjoyed
much respect even among scholars. In his 60th year he was
called to a professorship at Cologne. Heinrich von Virneburg—a
Franciscan, unfavourable to Dominicans, anyway—was the
archbishop there, and it was before his court that the now
immensely popular Meister Eckhart was first formally charged
with heresy. To a list of errors, he replied by publishing a
Latin Defense and then asked to be transferred to the pope’s
court in Avignon. When ordered to justify a new series of
propositions drawn from his writings, he declared: “I may
err but I am not a heretic, for the first has to do with the
mind and the second with the will!” Before judges who had no
comparable mystical experience of their own, Eckhart
referred to his inner certainty: “What I have taught is the
naked truth.” The bull of Pope John XXII, dated March 27,
1329, condemns 28 propositions extracted from the two lists.
Since it speaks of Meister Eckhart as already dead, it is
inferred that Eckhart died some time before, perhaps in 1327
or 1328. It also says that Eckhart had retracted the errors
as charged.
Although Eckhart’s philosophy amalgamates Greek,
Neoplatonic, Arabic, and Scholastic elements, it is unique.
His doctrine, sometimes abstruse, always arises from one
simple, personal mystical experience to which he gives a
number of names. By doing so, he was also an innovator of
the German language, contributing many abstract terms. In
the second half of the 20th century, there was great
interest in Eckhart among some Marxist theorists and Zen
Buddhists.
Reiner Schürmann
|
Medieval philosophy » The late Middle Ages » Nicholas of Cusa
Nicholas of Cusa (1401–64) also preferred the Neoplatonists to the
Aristotelians. To him the philosophy of Aristotle is an obstacle to the
mind in its ascent to God because its primary rule is the principle of
contradiction, which denies the compatibility of contradictories. But
God is the “coincidence of opposites.” Because he is infinite, he
embraces all things in perfect unity; he is at once the maximum and the
minimum. Nicholas uses mathematical symbols to illustrate how, in
infinity, contradictories coincide. If a circle is enlarged, the curve
of its circumference becomes less; if a circle is infinite, its
circumference is a straight line. As for human knowledge of the infinite
God, one must be content with conjecture or approximation to the truth.
The absolute truth escapes human beings; their proper attitude is
“learned ignorance.”
For Nicholas, God alone is absolutely infinite. The universe reflects
this divine perfection and is relatively infinite. It has no
circumference, for it is limited by nothing outside of itself. Neither
has it a centre; the Earth is neither at the centre of the universe nor
is it completely at rest. Place and motion are not absolute but relative
to the observer. This new, non-Aristotelian conception of the universe
anticipated some of the features of modern theories.
Thus, at the end of the Middle Ages, some of the most creative minds
were abandoning Aristotelianism and turning to newer ways of thought.
The philosophy of Aristotle, in its various interpretations, continued
to be taught in the universities, but it had lost its vitality and
creativity. Christian philosophers were once again finding inspiration
in Neoplatonism. The Platonism of the Renaissance was directly
continuous with the Platonism of the Middle Ages.
The Rev. Armand Maurer, C.S.B.

|
Nicholas of Cusa
Christian scholar
German Nikolaus Von Cusa, Latin Nicolaus Cusanus
born 1401, Kues, Trier
died Aug. 11, 1464, Todi, Papal States
Main
cardinal, mathematician, scholar, experimental scientist,
and influential philosopher who stressed the incomplete
nature of man’s knowledge of God and of the universe.
At the Council of Basel in 1432, he gained recognition
for his opposition to the candidate put forward by Pope
Eugenius IV for the archbishopric of Trier. To his
colleagues at the council he dedicated De concordantia
catholica (1433; “On Catholic Concordance”), in which he
expressed support for the supremacy of the general councils
of the church over the authority of the papacy. In the same
work he discussed the harmony of the church, drawing a
pattern for priestly concord from his knowledge of the order
of the heavens. By 1437, however, finding the council
unsuccessful in preserving church unity and enacting needed
reforms, Nicholas reversed his position and became one of
Eugenius’ most ardent followers. Ordained a priest about
1440, Cusa was made a cardinal in Brixen (Bressanone),
Italy, by Pope Nicholas V and in 1450 was elevated to bishop
there. For two years Cusa served as Nicholas’ legate to
Germany, after which he began to serve full-time as bishop
of Brixen.
A model of the “Renaissance man” because of his
disciplined and varied learning, Cusa was skilled in
theology, mathematics, philosophy, science, and the arts. In
De docta ignorantia (1440; “On Learned Ignorance”) he
described the learned man as one who is aware of his own
ignorance. In this and other works he typically borrowed
symbols from geometry to demonstrate his points, as in his
comparison of man’s search for truth to the task of
converting a square into a circle.
Among Cusa’s other interests were diagnostic medicine and
applied science. He emphasized knowledge through
experimentation and anticipated the work of the astronomer
Copernicus by discerning a movement in the universe that did
not centre in the Earth, although the Earth contributed to
that movement. Cusa’s study of plant growth, from which he
concluded that plants absorb nourishment from the air, was
the first modern formal experiment in biology and the first
proof that air has weight. Numerous other developments,
including a map of Europe, can also be traced to Cusa. A
manuscript collector who recovered a dozen lost comedies by
the Roman writer Plautus, he left an extensive library that
remains a centre of scholarly activity in the hospital he
founded and completed at his birthplace in 1458.
|
|